History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment of Vl

That's French for "the ancient system," as in the ancient system of feudal privileges and the exercise of autocratic power over the peasants. The ancien regime never goes away, like vampires and dinosaur bones they are always hidden in the earth, exercising a mysterious influence. It is not paranoia to believe that the elites scheme against the common man. Inform yourself about their schemes here.

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 1:18 am

Part 1 of 4

III. Philosophy of History in Solov'ev

The true unity of humanity and the hoped-for peace must be based not upon the weakness and subjugation of nations but upon the highest development of their powers and a free interaction between nationalities which serve as a complement to one another. [1]


Introduction

From the very outset of his career, Solov'ev was concerned with the category of progressive development. This category is central in 19th century philosophy of history that developed an examination of world history both in its immanence and in its global nature. Solov'ev found support in this register to emphasise three main points: history, including non-religious institutions, has to be valued positively, and can be directed by men, who gather in a supra-entity, humanity. In PH, in contrast to TH, history is not seen as mere contingency opposed to the true being which is eternity, but is examined in its intrinsic value. Secular forms of collectivity, such as the state and the nation, have to be valued positively. In addition, progress is not initiated and directed by a transcendent plan, but is a law immanent to the subject changing, is initiated from within by men. This view implies that the subject in question is a harmonious entity. Solov'ev identified the chief subject of this process as humanity. In a teleological perspective, he posed that humanity is evolving by virtue of a single metaphysical principle, which he defined as 'all-unity' [vseedinstvo]. All-unity governs the historical process from within and is the goal towards which humanity as a whole is striving, and which it will realise. In this sense, all-unity functions as the metaphysical principle that structures Solov'ev's philosophy of history and can be considered the philosophical equivalent of Bogocelovecestvo. With this concept, Solov'ev strove to pose the values of both individual freedom and collectivity as criteria for historical action. [2] In doing so, he struggled against the tendency to sacrifice the former term, as Pobedonoscev, the neo-Slavophiles and the socialists did, as well as against the neglect or negation of collectivity such as in liberal and subjectivist thought. This also applies to the most comprehensive form of collectivity, humanity, the ontological existence and unity of which Solov'ev defended against nationalist views on history. In this respect, his philosophy of history allowed him to defend universalism on the basis of an immanent conception of history.

In my opinion, Solov'ev developed a philosophy of history of his own, which includes Hegelian and Comtian elements, and bears the influence of his father, Sergej Mikhailovic Solov'ev. Solov'ev did not produce a systematic philosophy of history backed by a great number of facts, as did Hegel, Comte, or Spengler. Nevertheless, he offered broad interpretations of world history, which testify to his powerful and historical range of vision. However, in his effort to simultaneously show continuity and change in world history, his approach remained on the whole highly general, which resulted in a schematic discourse on progress. In the scarce places where he elaborated on history, Solov'ev operated highly selectively with respect to historical data. What strikes the reader is the constant effort to connect these data to a progressive line of history, and to its universal significance within this line. He mainly elaborates on philosophy of history in the introduction to Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, entitled 'Obsceistoriceskoe vvedenie (ol zakone istoriceskogo razvitija)' [General-Historical Introduction (about the Law of Historical Development)], and in Opravdanie dobra. A wide range of other publications also contains elements of philosophy of history, which I use in this analysis.

In order to understand the working of the philosophical register of history in Solov'ev's work, in the first part of this section (1) I deal with (a) his definition of history in philosophical terms, (b) the general framework, (c) periodisations and underlying conception of time, (d) method and criteria, and (e) the actors that play a major role in history. In the second part (2), I examine the relationship of Solov'ev's philosophy of history with that of (a) Hegel, (b) Sergej Solov'ev, and (c) Comte.

1. The Register of Philosophy of History in Solov'ev

a) General definition


Characteristically, it is difficult to find in Solov'ev's work a single definition of history that is entirely formulated in the philosophical register, as it always contains Christian elements or a sophianic colouring. Significantly, rather than defining the term 'history', Solov'ev offers various characteristics of 'historical development' and the 'historical process.' His outspoken preference for such expressions strongly suggests that he saw philosophy of history as the best available means of describing history in terms of continuity, in its immanence and in its concrete forms.

In Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija he announced that the main objective of his examination of history was to solve the question of the goal of human existence. [3] He hereby from the outset established a teleological perspective that remained constant in his work. This goal is common to all men, since it is connected to the life of all people. It is also intrinsic to them as the formal and final cause of their development. [4] He identified this goal as 'integral life organisation' or 'all-unity.' [5] In all-unity, a balance is obtained at the level of humanity between individual freedom and unity of the community. [6] A goal also implies development leading up to it, in which one should take part collectively. This is made possible by the fact that this final goal is understandable to every human being and can be defined in broad lines. [7] For it is not enough to be conscious of this goal:

History (and consequently the world process as a whole) has a goal, which we undoubtedly know, an all-embracing goal which at the same time is sufficiently determined for us to consciously participate in its achievement. [8]


The observation that history is goal-oriented implies active participation in its realisation. We can therefore reconstruct the following syllogism: history is an immanent goal-oriented process; this goal is knowable and achievable; everything knowable and achievable must be done; thus the human collectivity has to contribute to the realisation of this goal.

To sum up, in Solov'ev's philosophy of history, history can be defined as the gradual realisation of all-unity through collective action.

b) Framework


In his philosophy of history, Solov'ev focused on the world alone, namely on the immanent development of humanity towards all-unity, regardless of the transcendent level of divine agency. The framework of history is structured by one and the same global principle of development, to which all beings, whether individual, national, or universal, are subjected. The priority of the principle of a single continuous development determines the general outline of history in Solov'ev as a primarily linear, rather than cyclical, or dialectical, scheme. [9]

In order to build his conception of teleological development as an immanent process on a firm basis, Solov'ev turned to the organicistic model of explanation. The analogy between human society and a biological organism offers three main advantages. Firstly, it permits an understanding of human society, and thus by extension, history, as an immanent entity moving forward on the basis of its own force, not that of God as in theology of history. [10] Secondly, it presupposes that there is a certain unity or continuity of evolution between the natural and the human realm, within the immanent world, i.e. between nature and culture. [11] Solov'ev discussed, mainly with reference to Darwin, the biological and psychological evolution of animals into human beings, even though his interest in evolutionism focused on human beings and human society. [12] The framework of his philosophy of history is shaped by the evolution of the collective forms of human existence towards the ideal society, that is, organic unity or solidarity at all levels: local, national, and universal.

In addition to the unity of the temporal framework, which is thoroughly structured by the category of progressive development, Solov'ev posited the unity of the spatial or geographical framework. Two factors come to the fore in Solov'ev's approach. On the one hand, the main actor and ultimate achiever of all-unity is humanity in its entirety, i.e. humanity realising its potency. In this respect, the third advantage of the organicistic metaphor is that it permits an intrinsic link between the parts and the whole, similar to the link between organs and the organism. This notably implies a mutual influence between the individual, the various forms of collectivity, and humanity as a whole. [13] On the other hand, Solov'ev divided humanity into several groups and sketched a movement of history from East to West, from the Middle and Near East to Europe. He largely left out America, Africa, and Oceania, and displayed a strong Eurocentrism, which included Russia and which found support in the idea of cultural imperialism. [14] According to the latter, to which Solov'ev adhered, Europe, including Russia, was the starting point for bringing true values to humanity as a whole and realising (all-)unity of the whole planet. It is precisely this goal, and the immanent development leading to it, which are the objects of Solov'ev's philosophy of history.

c) Periodisation and conception of time

i) Periodisation


Properly speaking we find in Solov'ev only one periodisation of world history, namely in the first chapter of Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija. Significantly, the succinctness of this survey (only about twenty pages!) reveals that Solov'ev was interested in general lines rather than in particular events. In an attempt to deal with human activities exhaustively, he divided these into the theoretical (theology, philosophy, science), practical (spiritual, political, economic society), and creative (mysticism, fine arts, technical arts) fields. Examining their evolution throughout history, he posed that history is made up of three successive phases, undifferentiated unity, separation, and differentiated unity between and within these fields. [15] These three phases as it were form Solov'ev's universal law of historical development. In the first phase, which took place in Ancient India, Greece, and Rome, the three fields were not differentiated. [16] Later on, after the distinction between theory, practice, and creation had occurred, a fusion still remained within each of the three fields, for example, in knowledge, between theology, philosophy, and science. A second phase began with the appearance of Christianity, which introduced the separation of the sacred from the profane. In this phase Western civilisation dominated, which excessively distinguished between all fields of human activities. For instance, in practical life, church, state, and economy were separated. Besides, each of these successively played the leading role in Western history, ending with the domination of economics, as was claimed by socialism in Solov'ev's time. [17] In a near future, a third phase of synthesis or differentiated unity, would follow, in which 'human development' would realise its 'absolute content.' In this phase, the reconciliation would take place between the forces of the first (mainly Eastern) and second (mainly Western) phase. The task of performing this reconciliation would be that of the Slavic people, especially Russia. Solov'ev characterised this phase in religious terms, and thus at this point left open the register of pure philosophy of history [see synthesis Part Two].

In Opravdanie dobra, he completed the general picture of world history by examining, in the first place, what we could identify as the phase preceding the process sketched above. Solov'ev comprehensively analysed the evolution of human community from the clan through Eastern monarchies up to the state. [18] Solov'ev borrowed much of the argumentation from Sergej Solov'ev for this account [see subsection 2b]. In the second place, he depicted the progressive unification of humanity in secular terms, by pointing to the intensification of internal relationships and the globalisation of culture [see Aei-ii).

We may conclude that, rather than in periodisations per se, Solov'ev seemed interested in certain episodes in history, the interval between which he might have considered as periods, but which he did not examine as such. This is most obvious in his treatment of Russian history. Solov'ev pointed to three fundamental episodes: first the call to the Varangians in the 9th century, second the opening towards Europe under Peter I, and third the abolition of serfdom under Alexander II. [19] As a matter of fact, Solov'ev's teleological perspective on history dictates a tendency to examine the events that are constitutive for the establishment of the goal, rather than examining the phases between those events, which would require more detailed investigations.

ii) Conception of time

Solov'ev hardly ever devoted special attention to the question of time. In the short entry 'Vremja' [Time] written for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, he approached time in a Kantian manner as a universal form of Anschauung. He argued that no explanation of time could be given on an empirical or rational basis, but rather that philosophical elaborations on time all had a metaphysical character. [20] It appears therefore that Solov'ev, in contrast with transcendental philosophy, did not consider time a philosophical issue independently from metaphysics. [21] He only mentioned the contribution made by Kant in the conceptualisation of time, yet did not either elaborate on it or propose his own vision on the topic. [22] Nor did he broach the topic of historical time as such, which generally includes a definition of its main components, namely past, present, and future, an analysis of the perception of these by man, as well as an interpretation of the mutual relationships between past, present, and future. One can explain this absence of reflection by the fact that he deliberately reflected on history from a speculative, universalistic, and eternalistic standpoint, from which all questions related to time were unproblematic. Characteristically, he neither questioned nor justified the very standpoint he adopted. Consequently, a personal experience of time such as that which initiated and nurtured Augustine's reflections, for instance, was not relevant for Solov'ev.

Although time is not addressed in Solov'ev, it plays no less fundamental a role than in any other discourse on history. The principles of teleology and continuity that are so determinant in Solov'ev, dictate a certain view on the phenomenon of change in time. Holding to the idea that that which appears as novelty is only the concrete realisation or actualisation of an element that was already working in some form, he interpreted problems of the present as the result of an entire historical process. Besides, he sensed that history had accelerated since the end of the eighteenth century, and felt that Europe and Russia were rapidly changing. [23] As far as his conception of future is concerned, Solov'ev was, like most philosophers of history of his century, deeply optimistic. [24] He perceived the future as the open dimension in which man would be able to implement the final goal of universal solidarity. This goal should be attained while preserving a link of continuity with the past, that is, a respect for the work achieved by ancestors and their values, in short a respect for tradition. Solov'ev's philosophical conception of time is therefore marked by a dynamic tension between an attachment to the past and the effort required to create a future different from the present. [25] In his PH he emphasised man's capacity to achieve this ideal in the future.

d) Criteria and method

i) Criterion: progress


Solov'ev considered progress to be a fundamental force shaping history into a single ascending line. This concept rests on the major contribution made by European science, which, towards the end of the 18th century, developed the concept of a unified and determined historical process. [26] In his eyes, progress in practice included regressions and stagnations, yet improvement remains predominant:

In spite of all the vacillation and the zigzagging of progress, in spite of all of today's exacerbation of militarism, nationalism, anti-Semitism, terrorism, and so on and so forth -- for all that, the fact that the resultant force of history is going from cannibalism toward love of fellowman, from lawlessness to justice, and from hostile disconnection of particular groups toward universal solidarity remains
doubtless. [27]


As is obvious from this passage, Solov'ev needed the concept of progress because of one functional aspect: the structuring of historical phenomena along one single line leading to the goal of all-unity. [28] He had taken great care to preliminarily define this goal, notably because he was opposed to progress that was deprived of any goal, or indefinite progress, as well as to a progress without an end, an endless progress. [29] Progress is also something necessary, in two respects, Firstly, it occurs as the necessary result of inner motives nurtured by individuals and nations. Secondly, it is made up of stages that were and are necessary. Hereby is the meaning of history itself justified. For instance, wild humanity had to go through despotism to overcome it and become civilised. [30] In this respect, Solov'ev's view was akin to Hegel, Comte, and Marx, who all believed in the necessary succession of given stages.

Beside its structuring function, the idea of progress allows the legitimisation of continuity. [31] Solov'ev offered a challenging argumentation on this point. On the one hand, true progress, especially moral progress, implies a conservative attitude, an attachment to tradition: 'moral progress can only consist in a better and wider fulfilling of the obligations which derive from tradition.' [32] Tradition transmits certain principles of order, because, if it was anything other than order, tradition would have disappeared.
In other terms, progress is not the negation of order, but rather the progress of order. [33] On the other hand, true progress implies the introduction of positive innovation. In connection to this, Solov'ev defined progress in opposition to stagnation, for which he used the term kitaizm, 'Chin ism" to point to 'the exclusive concern with a traditional order that has been undermined [podkopannogo] from all sides.' [34]

The link that the philosopher formulated between continuity and change shows that he was against what we could call 'progress by making tabula rasa.' He was fiercely opposed to the socialist interpretation of progress coming from revolution that was fashionable in the Russian populist press of the I870s. [35] In his eyes, this conception of progress had been dominant in Western European debates since the 18th century, and implied a chiefly negative relationship to the past, because it rejected the past order en bloc. [36] This was therefore equivalent to suppressing the very essence of progress. A radical break with the past generations would have fatal consequences and was for him equivalent to a destruction of 'the unity of that which develops itself or progresses, i.e. most of all the real inner solidarity of the old and the new generations of progressing humanity.' [37] The motive of Solov'ev's deep-seated aversion against revolution thus lies in the potential destruction of the unity with the past, and, as a result, of humanity. His conviction that positive development was already an embryonic component of the present, and should be introduced gradually, sustained his belief in progress by means of reform instead of revolution.

In conformity with the common tendency in philosophy of history, Solov'ev distinguished between different types of progress that touched upon the most varied of human activities: moral, social, political, technical, cultural, and spiritual progress. [38] Three general factors of progress had been operating from the Middle Ages onwards: the development of nationalities [razvitie nacional'nosti], the corresponding development of international relationships, and the geographical extension of the unity of culture to the entire globe, or, in present-day terms, the globalisation of culture [see next subsection on humanity and nations.] [39]

Interestingly, Solov'ev also brought war to the fore as a motor of progress. Here we encounter one of the very few historical analyses made by Solov'ev entirely in the register of philosophy of history. [40] War, he argued, 'has been the chief historical means of bringing about the external political unification of humanity.' [41] War had first led to the formation of states. It had then initiated other positive developments such as the abolition of war within the states' own boundaries, conditions for a mutual rapprochement between the states, a reduction of active military forces for more effective results, and a decrease in the number of human lives sacrificed. Solov'ev stated that war had also played an active role as a condition of technical and scientific progress in the nineteenth century, and in the propagation of ideas in general. Apart from the question whether war in itself promoted the above-mentioned developments, one can note that his considerations in no way address the question of the damage caused by war, such as the destruction of cultural heritage. Generally, he perceived a progress towards fewer conflicts; they were becoming shorter and more rare, from which he concluded that humanity would witness the end of war. [42] His treatment of the phenomenon of war shows that on the very few occasions that that the philosopher made a historical analysis, his perspective was restricted to the point, namely on war as a factor of unification.

Solov'ev also pointed out progress as far as Russian history was concerned, albeit in low key. When he commented on the abolition of serfdom, he ironically explained that there had actually been no moral progress between the heroes of Homer and the Russian landowners of the 1840s. [43] It was only in the last thirty years (1865-1895) that an elevation of moral demands had occurred through the abolition of serfdom in Russia, parallel to the abolition of slavery in the United States of America (1865). What had happened, he argued, was that an idea that had been so far restricted to the subjective area of morality had now become a common and objective task. [44] For progress to become objective, an idea had first to reach collective awareness. The main tool for fostering this awareness is the use of speculative reason.

ii) Method: speculative reason

Speculative reason, and its main device deduction, is the key instrument used by Solov'ev to convince his fellow men of the rationality of the historical world and to exhort them to take active part in the historical process towards all-unity. The result of his accounts, however, is often disappointing. The philosopher applied deduction in a hastened way, and as a result strongly simplified history in order to integrate particular episodes in his own picture. He carried out these simplifications in three ways. Firstly, by defining a phenomenon on the basis of an abstract principle, for instance 'Byzantinism', the manifestation of which he quickly deduced from historical events, he ended up yielding historical misinterpretations and circular arguments. [45] Secondly, by imposing his law of historical development, he was highly selective. [46] Thirdly, as a result of this approach, characterised by the exclusive search for signs and symptoms in history that could confirm his thesis, he tended to reduce collective historical participation to the action of its most prominent figures, mostly political leaders. In the description of an epoch, he often limited himself to portraying individual deeds of heroes, such as Vladimir, Peter I, Catherine II and Alexander II. Such an arrangement of the world can be justified only speculatively, which the philosopher did by untiringly pointing to the goal of all-unity, out of which all empirical things could be deduced. [47] He showed himself reluctant to take historical experience for more than a verification of his own metaphysical theses.

Speculative reason can nevertheless find assistance in the empirical examination of sources, which is at work in historical science. One of Solov'ev's very few reflective moments on the relationship between philosophy and history is a review of the historical journal run by his old school companion, historian Nikolaj Kareev. [48] Solov'ev contested the claim made by the historian that philosophy relates to subjective data, and historical science to objective data, and attempted to show philosophy as contributor to 'a theory of the world process.' [49] Against Kareev's defence of a separation between philosophy and historical science, Solov'ev pleaded for cooperation between the two fields, in which he proposed the following division of labour. Philosophers pointed to general principles, to paths of reflection, such as the explanation of the unity that makes up history, while historians provided concrete objects of reflection. [50] He argued that Kareev's distinction between objective and subjective, used to differentiate the work of the historian from that of the philosopher, was irrelevant, for that what is true subjectively, is true objectively. He replaced the dichotomy objectivity/subjectivity by the dichotomy true/false, but did not answer the question about what the criteria of truth are. [51] By this omission, he placed truth, which he considered the norm, by which we should judge history, above method. So even within an epistemological reflection, his philosophical account of history often results in a dogmatic discourse.

The division of labour between philosophers and historians did not however stop him from applying the main method of historians, namely the use of sources such as empirical observations made by others, on a number of occasions. The manner in which he treated the famine of 1891-1892 is a brilliant and rare counter-example to his usual deductive method. He made use of geographical and statistic data, and outlined the worsening of the peasant situation over the last decades in factual terms [see case study V 'The famine of 1891- 1892']. Solov'ev also turned to the empirical method for other studies that, with rare exceptions, can be situated on the border between empirical and speculative history. [52] Characteristically, in his sketch of the formation of the character of a people, Solov'ev investigated neither the historical life of peoples in their concrete variety, nor for instance external influences such as climate, but addressed precisely an issue that can hardly be submitted to empirical investigation, namely the origin of the national character. [53] He ascribed the latter to the character of the founder of the clan [rodonacal'nik] and pointed to the religious dimension at work, hereby situating himself on the border between phenomenal history and religion. [54]

In sum, Solov'ev operated mostly with speculative reason in his philosophical register on history in order to demonstrate that the pervasiveness of the principle of all-unity was being realised. Because of a lack of historical data, the results of these accounts are mostly unconvincing.

e) Actors

Man not only understands the rational meaning of history, but shapes history through the participation of an increasingly large community. For a philosopher of history, the challenge consists in emphasising the agency of larger groups without neglecting the plurality of the individuals:

The true subject of moral progress -- as well as of historical progress in general -- is the individual man together and inseparably from collective man or society. [55]


According to Solov'ev, the forms of this collective being are most of all humanity, the nations, and the state; great (states)men form the prominent category of individual actors.

i) Humanity

Throughout Solov'ev's work, humanity is the chief subject of history: 'The subject of development here is humanity as a real, though also collective organism.' [56] The role of the organicistic model for the definition of humanity as an immanent and autonomous force has been pointed out above [see subsection I b]. [57] With respect to humanity, the analogy also permits a distinction between, on the one hand, humanity's organs, or composite parts, i.e. nations, and, on the other hand, the systems that form it and which are common to all nations, i.e. knowledge, practical activity and creation. [58] On the basis of this programmatic statement, one would expect Solov'ev to examine all these domains in the context of their development in one or several nations, and observe the complementary character of these contributions from the perspective of humanity. However, as we have seen, the philosopher did not elaborate on any of these domains and only offered sketches. Obviously, he was most eager to integrate all the composing elements into the totalising perspective, rather than in a precise analysis of the multiple forms of manifestation of and interrelationships between these categories.

It is a recurring feature in Solov'ev's work to advocate a consideration of national developments from the perspective of humanity. He stated that 'civilised humanity' as a whole was rising, which tended 'increasingly to become the whole of humanity.' [59] What did he mean precisely? International relationships had intensified, a world market had appeared, as well as a 'constant collaboration of all civilised countries in technical and scientific work', and inventions in communication media and transport, which suppressed geographical distance. [60] In his eyes, the same process included the penetration of European culture in increasing numbers of areas, and thus, colonialism, which he regarded highly as a propagator of civilised culture to the whole planet. [61] By the 1890s, when he equated civilised culture with European culture, Solov'ev showed himself a eurocentrist and at the same time a universalist, in his own terms, a Westerniser. [62]

As a matter of fact, it was Solov'ev's fundamental contribution to the Russian tradition of philosophy of history to conceive of history from a consistently universalist perspective. [63] In his early years, he focused on Russia's mission, and later, moored Russia's history to that of the West by interpreting it on the basis of the criteria of the Enlightenment: freedom, emancipation, and progress [see case studies IV and V). At stake was the extension of solidarity to humanity as a whole, which should not be realised at the expense of individual rights. In this respect, his motivation to engage in a polemic with the Russian proponent of the theory of separate cultural types, Nikolaj Danilevskij, also becomes clear. Against the view that a cultural type develops separately and does not transmit its values to others, Solov'ev was eager to defend the conception of humanity as an organic whole, structured by strong relationships. This whole, humanity, he saw precisely as the ontological and epistemological condition for the universalisation of the good. [64]

This scheme of gradual unification of humanity is challenged by another, similarly powerful scheme in his work, namely that of a humanity divided into two conflicting components, East and West. The antagonism between the Eastern and the Western world is one of Solov'ev's most permanent historical topics, not only in theological, but also in philosophical terms. [65] Solov'ev filled these categories with varying geographical contents. The East meant first the Middle-East (India), then Eastern Christianity (Byzantium), and finally, with a sharper perception of the 'yellow peril', the Far East (China and Japan). [66] As to the notion of Europe, he regarded it first as excluding Russia, then as including it, but only up to a certain point, because his fatherland perfectly embodied the conflict between East and West, between exclusive conservatism and progress.

However, this conflict between East and West was not to last forever. The Russian philosopher was convinced that humanity was not ontologically determined by this dichotomy, but could and should be unified because it was in essence a unity. [67] In this sense, he was not a civilisationist, and his polemic with Danilevskij confirms his universalist position. He predicted that the struggle between East and West would continue between the two halves of the world, in a future armed struggle between Europe and Mongol Asia, which would be the last war, a world war. The victory of one of them would ensure 'peace to the rest of the world', and a 'world empire' or world monarchy would be established. [68] In this way, he believed that humanity was destined to ultimately become one.

ii) Nations


Solov'ev did not offer a systematic view on the role of nations in world history, as did Hegel or Danilevskij, but only a short survey in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, a more extensive overview in Opravdanie dobra, and passages in various works. [69] They testify, if not to his sustained interest in the question, to his range of vision. In these surveys he showed himself to be a typical nineteenth century thinker, in the sense that, at least since Herder, it was common to reflect on history in terms of historical nations. [70]

Solov'ev considered nations to be central categories of world history and consistently related their existence to humanity. [71] He picked up on four fundamental Hegelian characterisations of the nation [see subsection 2aii] and more specifically described the character of certain nations on the basis of their historical achievements, mostly in the fields of art, science and culture (Italy, Germany, England, Poland, Russia), religion (Spain, Germany) and civil rights (England, France). [72] Spain served humanity by defending Europe against Islam. [73] The English nation developed geniuses in literature and science, brought to the fore the principles of religious and civil freedom, which influenced the formation of the United States of America, and had scientists who demonstrated the physical unity of the universe. England also succeeded in expanding civilisation to India and Australia. Whereas France introduced the idea of human rights, Germany contributed to world history with the Reformation, poetry, Kant and Hegel's philosophy. Solov'ev focused on national geniuses, dropping names in art and science, and hastily mentioned significant religious events and conquests in order to produce this hurried picture of national characters. If a nation is true to its idea, he held, it does not attach an absolute significance to its material interest, but only to its ideal, universal mission, and that it feels this universal dimension in itself.

The essential message that Solov'ev wanted to convey was clear: the significance of a nation is determined by its contribution to humanity. From this perspective, a theory such as that of Danilevskij on cultural types, which denied the supra-unity of humanity, was totally incoherent. He found it also to be invalidated by current developments, such as an intensification of internal exchange in politics, economy and culture. [74] However, Sternkopf's conclusion that he totally subordinated the existence of nations to humanity is exaggerated. [75] Solov'ev's valuation of the existence of nations was undeniably positive. These nations could only achieve what they achieved by virtue of their particularity, and were bound to remain until the end of history.

By arguing that nations find their essential meaning in humanity, he was aiming at two targets. Firstly, he sought to formulate a consistent answer to the supporters of nationalism. His point was that a nation lives only in the supra-national and international environment, only in relationship to humanity and to other nations. [76] Unfortunately, this remains one of the least developed aspects of his philosophy of history. Secondly, and more fundamentally, by claiming that 'the reason for the existence of nations does not find itself in them, but in humanity', he was pointing out what he considered the main priority, or in other terms, the ideal entity to be realised in the future, namely all-unity or universal solidarity. [77] His emphasis that this goal should be realised by man makes his philosophy of history a call for action. From a teleological perspective, he kept emphasising humanity, and only briefly described the formation of such and such a nation.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 1:19 am

Part 2 of 4

iii) The state

From a general point of view, one has to make the distinction between two understandings of the term 'state' [gosudarstvo]. There is the state in the broad sense and the state in the narrow sense. The state in the broad sense is 'a nation or territory considered as an organised political community under a government.' This is similar to 'nation' in Solov'ev's understanding of the term, with emphasis on the aspect of internal organisation. [78] The state in the narrow sense is 'the civil government of a country', as the particular political institution within the nation. [79] Solov'ev neither made this distinction nor developed a theory of the state, but offered reflections on state both in the broad and the narrow sense. [80]

Influenced by his father and through him by Hegel, Solov'ev viewed the state as the culminating point of the evolution of human organisation [on these influences, see part 2 of this chapter]. The state acquired not only the conservative task of protecting the basis of social life, but also a progressive one, namely improving the conditions of that life. [81] The social task of the state was made possible if the state concentrated in its own hands those means of production and distribution that are purely material (factories, banks, infrastructure, lines of communication, firms) in order to guarantee minimal material good for everyone. [82] In a liberal stance, however Solov'ev also defended the preservation of private property. This position shows how he strove to preserve both individuality and collectivity in his system.

In addition to the above, Solov'ev also relativised the role of the state. In his theocratic scheme, in which the state turns out to be only one of the three highest instances, he posed that the power should be shared by church, state, and zemstvo. [83] He also stated that a perversion of the idea of the state, for instance by those who place it above moral law such as Hobbes, Hegel and Marx, is a specific evil. [84] Another reason he gave for relativising the role of state is that it is a particular organism that does not deal with universal interests and, in this respect, is limited. [85] Solov'ev primarily considered the state from a universal perspective. As to the regime of the state, Solov'ev believed in monarchy as the best possible form for the realisation of all-unity. [86] Accordingly, he suggested that the idea of a universal state or world monarchy, even though it had not been realised politically so far, would be the ideal political form of all-unity. [87]

iv) Great (states)men and common individuals


The category of great men is certainly the least original in Solov'ev's philosophy of history. He may have picked it up directly from Hegel, or indirectly through Sergej Solov'ev [see subsection 2a and 2b]. Great men are called 'best men, heroes, motors [dvigateli] of history.' [88] These enlightened personalities are an elite that introduces a new level of consciousness, and represents the dynamic element, opposed to the static established order. [89] These heroes are often builders of nations or states. [90] They are also sometimes the cultural representatives of national genius, such as poets and thinkers. [91] The political leaders especially are rough people, who do not accept any limits. However, Solov'ev neither further elaborated the category of great men nor applied it concretely to great figures of (Russian) history. This raises the question of his real interest in history as a whole. Arguably, he made use of certain events and figures in order to illustrate his theses about the embodiment of morality in history, rather than analysing them for their own sake. [92] In other words, although one cannot deny that his thought was embedded in a historical mould, his use of historical elements often bears an instrumental character.

Concerning ordinary individuals, he emphasised their role by arguing that the individual had always been 'the active principle of historical progress.' [93] Hereby Solov'ev aimed at the socialist perspective, which emphasised the group, collectivity as the main actor of history, at the expense of the individual. His interest in the category of the individual is well known. [94] At the same time, this did not stop him from fiercely criticising individualism, for instance in Lev Tolstoj's moral subjectivism. [95] He emphasised the possibility, and the obligation, for everyone to act well, as a way of taking part in the general progressive movement of history. [96]

In sum, Solov'ev organised a set of views that bear the stamps of nineteenth-century philosophy of history on the basis of the metaphysical principle of all-unity, namely the definition of history as a single goal-oriented process sustained by an optimistic view of progress and described in rationalistic terms. [97] Hereby he sought to enlighten history from the point of view of its immanent processes. He succeeded in establishing humanity as chief subject of history, and consistently, though often schematically, related the historical nations and the state to humanity. The following section deals with the question of the role of three major authors, namely Sergej Solov'ev, Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, and Auguste Comte, in shaping his philosophy of history.

2. The Dialogue

Solov'ev engaged in discussion with many philosophers during the course of his career. As far as his philosophy of history is concerned, two major protagonists appear on the foreground, namely Hegel and Comte. Prior to them, however, he was subject to the influence of his father, Sergej Solov'ev, who apart from being a prominent historian, also developed a philosophy of history from a strongly Hegelian perspective.

In this section, I investigate the reception of the Hegelian and the Comtian philosophy of history by Vladimir Solov'ev. I depart from his explicit comments on the two philosophers, and then conduct a specific investigation of the Hegelian and Comtian elements in his view. As a matter of fact, one cannot fully rely on Solov'ev's own statements on these authors for two reasons. Firstly, Solov'ev overlooked several differences between the two authors, especially regarding their concept of development, as a result of a simplification of Hegelian dialectics. Secondly, although he heavily criticised Comte, he also implicitly assumed certain elements from him. My thesis is that Solov'ev took over the dialectical scheme of thesis-antithesis-synthesis for his survey of world history from Hegel [see Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija], and then neglected its most original component, namely conflict, or in Hegelian terms, negation and negation of negation. He also borrowed from Hegel, possibly through Sergej Solov'ev, the division of history into three main phases, the view of history moving from East to West, the historical role of nations, and the figures of historical heroes. From Comte he borrowed the aspect of linearity of progress, the definition of progress in combination with order, and possibly the division of history in three phases. He also had affinities with Comte's definition of humanity as historical subject. Apart from Hegel and Comte, and prior to them, Solov'ev was inspired by the worldview of his historian father. Sergej Solov'ev was practically the only generalist historian with whom Solov'ev dealt. My thesis is that Solov'ev borrowed the general framework of world history, the law of organic development and the Hegelian categories of historical actors, namely nations, the state, and the individual, directly from his father.

Two problems arise concerning the reception of Hegel and Comte. Firstly there is the question of the influence of Hegel on Sergej Solov'ev, and through him, on Vladimir Solov'ev. On the one hand, it often remains unclear whether Solov'ev borrowed aspects from Hegel directly, or indirectly via his father. On the other hand, whenever we encounter Hegelian views in Solov'ev that cannot be traced back to his reading Hegel, but which are present in Sergej Solov'ev's work, we can point to an indirect reception of Hegel via the historian. Therefore, it is crucial for the issue of the reception of Hegel by Solov'ev to include the work of Sergej Solov'ev and to acknowledge the significance of his influence on his son. Secondly, Hegel and Comte shared a number of views, which can be found in Vladimir Solov'ev. This makes it difficult to assess precisely the influence on him by the German or the French philosopher, or simply that of commonly shared views in his time. Therefore, whenever there is no textual evidence, my conclusions remain hypothetical.

For the sake of clarity, I do not approach the three authors chronologically, but start with Hegel (1770-1831), then discuss Sergej Solov'ev (1820-1879), and, thirdly, Comte (1798- 1857). In each case, I devote an introductory part to general issues related to Solov'ev's knowledge of works of these authors (i). In a second part, I focus on specific points of their philosophy of history that Solov'ev assumed, rejected, or discussed (ii).

a) Hegel

i) Introduction


This issue demands a comprehensive treatment if only because Hegel was probably the most influential philosopher of history in his century, so that the issue of the reception of his views by a Russian philosopher fifty years later is relevant in its own right. In addition, the question of the reception of Hegel by Solov'ev forms an important issue in Solov'ev scholarship. I claim that, on the whole, commentators have exaggerated the Hegelian legacy in Solov'ev's works and have been blinded by Solov'ev's own use of the same terminology -- the most obvious examples being 'dialectics', 'thesis', 'antithesis', and 'synthesis.' [98]

Solov'ev took a position on Hegel's philosophy of history specifically on many occasions. The irony is that in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, the twenty-four year-old Solov'ev proposed to bring Hegel's theory of development one step further and apply it to the field of history, apparently not knowing that Hegel had already accomplished this task himself in his Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte. [99] This analysis also deals with two texts which both contain elements taken from Hegel, namely La Sophia and Opravdanie dobra. [100] Besides, in his early writings in the 1870s, he commented on Hegel, and employed terms (re)introduced by Hegel such as 'dialectics' and 'historical process.' In his later years (1890s), he devoted an article to Hegel for the Russian Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia. [101]

This section aims to understand to what extent Solov'ev's philosophy of history is related to Hegel as its source of inspiration and object of critique. This, first, includes the question of which Hegelian elements Solov'ev acknowledged as explicitly having played a decisive role in his own reflections on history. The investigation must secondly examine to what extent these elements retain their Hegelian character when employed by Solov'ev. Thirdly, I discuss Solov'ev's critique of aspects of Hegelian philosophy of history. My hypothesis is that Hegel exerted a decisive, yet complex influence on Solov'ev's philosophy of history. Solov'ev integrated that what he considered useful in Hegel's system, namely certain elements of his conception of development and progress, and the central role of historical nations, the state, and great men. He also openly rejected Hegel's turning the state and reason into absolute concepts. However, he misinterpreted a central Hegelian component, namely dialectics. This investigation helps to discern to what extent Solov'ev's conception of history was a response to Hegel's philosophy of history, or an attempt to improve it, and to what extent we can speak of a Hegelian heritage when Solov'ev makes use of Hegelian terms in his philosophy of history.

So far, the issue of Solov'ev's reaction to Hegel's philosophy of history has not been extensively analysed by a specialist of Solov'ev and has only been the object of a few scholarly articles and isolated chapters within general works on Hegelianism in Russia. [102] The only study that deals specifically with our topic is the balanced article by J. L. Navickas. Navickas concludes that Hegel significantly influenced Solov'ev's doctrine of development, and at the same time indicates a radical difference between Hegel and Solov'ev's 'Christian historicism.' [103] Diverse claims have been made concerning Hegel's influence on Solov'ev's philosophical system as a whole. The Russian philosophy specialist, George Kline, has pointed to the profound influence that Hegel had on Solov'ev. [104] The opposed thesis can be read in the work of the expert of Hegelianism in Russia, Guy Planty-Bonjour, who, focusing mainly on Hegel's logic, concludes that Solov'ev remained highly remote from Hegel, in spite of his terminological borrowings. My analysis shows that Planty-Bonjour's conclusion applies especially to Solov'ev's philosophy of history.

ii) Solov'ev 's reception of Hegel's philosophy of history

It has been said of Hegel's philosophy of Right that it was the last testimony of a philosophical culture that understands itself explicitly as 'practical philosophy', in the sense of a methodical understanding of the 'whole' human (ethical as well as political, scientific and historical) 'praxis.' [105] The least we can say, if we drop the common occidentocentric perspective, is that Hegel was not the last. This statement is applicable to Vladimir Solov'ev as well, who aimed at regarding the 'whole human praxis' through the prism of historical development.

The conception of process (dialectics, development, progress)

The immense merit must be attributed to Hegel for having decisively established in science and in common consciousness the true and fruitful concepts of process, development, and history as the consequent [posledovatel'nogo] realisation of the ideal content. [106]

In his article for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, Solov'ev recognised the crucial contribution made by Hegel. If the concepts of process, development and history are in his eyes 'true and fruitful', he may have assumed them from Hegel. We have at least one testimony of his project, formulated as early as 1875, to integrate the Hegelian concept of world-process into his new system of universal religion. [107]

The latter rests upon Hegel's conception of dialectics, which is exposed in his Logic, and which underlies the whole system of the German philosopher. [108] The dialectical conception implies an active process that allows, through negation, the sublation [aufheben] of contradiction, making this contradiction creative. The presentation of dialectics is limited here to some elementary aspects. Dialectics describes the movement of the subject of history, the spirit [Geist], passing through three main stages: first it is posed in itself (an sich, thesis), then it develops out of itself and for itself in its manifestation (fur sich, antithesis), in order to return then into itself (an und fur sich, synthesis) and be with itself as an actualised and manifested being. The dialectic movement goes from abstraction to manifestation in concreteness by means of successive negations.

En-Sof in Hebrew literally means "there is no end...the very absolute as such, or positive nothing ...the principle of unconditional unity or 'unityness' as such, the principle of freedom from all forms, from all manifestations, and, consequently, from all being... eternally finds its opposite in itself, so that only through a relationship to this opposite can it assert itself, so that it is perfectly reciprocal."

-- Vladimir Solov'ev on Spiritual Nationhood, Russia and the Jews, by Judith Deutsch Kornblatt


In his theoretical writings Solov'ev reflected on the Hegelian dialectics from a metaphysical and logical point of view. [109] In 'Gegel', he valued Hegel's dialectics highly positively as a means by which the German philosopher had succeeded in establishing the conception of 'a living mobile trinity of moments' and arriving at 'a perfect identity of system and method.' [110] Concerning more specifically his application of dialectics to the field of history, we note a significant evolution in the course of his life. Starting from what comes across as an intentionally uncritical and full application in La Sophia, he later hardly ever used the term. Nevertheless, Solov'ev was most probably attracted to the Hegelian notion of historical process leading to a full unfolding.

In La Sophia, Solov'ev confessed to having learnt from Hegel that substance consists of the union of contraries, and that manifestation does not diminish the substance, but develops it. In this dialogue, Sophia herself suggests understanding history by means of dialectics. Significantly, dialectics are defined here as 'the unity of contraries' and referred to as a 'special philosophical science', characterised by the focus on 'the different phases of the process, or special forms of the ideal [ideel] world and their mutual relationship.' [111] Compared to the Hegelian understanding of dialectics, this short characterisation does not take into account the movement provoked by successive and numerous sublations [Aufhebungen], even if this is at best alluded to in the expression 'different phases.' Furthermore, Solov'ev offered a short overview of the cosmic and historical process in which tripartitions, negations, and syntheses abound. Dialectics seems to be used schematically to present a colourful picture, often difficult to follow, of the cosmic and historical process. [112] La Sophia can therefore be seen as Solov'ev's first attempt to apply Hegel's dialectics to philosophy of history, however intermingled with cosmic and sophiological elements it may have been. [113]

"God is the reconciliation of opposites," says the Sufi Karras.

-- Toward the One, by Pir Vilayat Inayat Khan


In Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija Solov'ev did not distinguish between Hegelian dialectics and the conception of organic development, and together called them 'law of development.' For Hegel, the dialectical process does include some form of organic development, yet applies to Spirit rather than to nature: development takes place through consciousness. Besides, it is precisely through this mediation that development encounters opposition and hindrance. [114] Perhaps mistaken by Hegel's frequent use of the organicistic metaphor, Solov'ev overlooked the pre-Darwinian distinction between unchanging nature and progressive Spirit made by the German philosopher. He mixed the two schemes in his definition of the law of development, explicitly stating that it had received its logical formulation in Hegel. [115] He did take over the Hegelian law of development, when positing that development comprises three phases, namely a first external, undifferentiated unity, sublated by a second phase of individuation and division, which in its turn is sublated by the third phase of unification as an internal and free link between all elements. [116] But he applied the law to the world as a whole, including nature [see his sophiology or history], and tended to ignore the element of negation.

After these initial statements, Solov'ev explicitly stated his intention to apply to history the law of development allegedly first formulated by Hegel, hereby presenting himself as Hegel's successor. He mainly adopted one central Hegelian aspect, namely the complex movement of abstract to concrete. [117] He also made an interesting move by extending the Hegelian model. The result was the following: whereas Hegel had applied dialectical development primarily to 'socio-moral and political human institutions' (cf. the Rechtsphilosophie), Solov'ev extended it to include creativity and knowledge, and placed 'all three on the same ontological and axiological level as essential components of "integral life".' [118] De Facto, Solov'ev described all three fields in their historical development in this text. However, countering Kline we must state that, even though Solov'ev's scheme may appear horizontal when compared with Hegel and indeed expanded dialectics to new fields, it is nevertheless structured in a vertical, hierarchical way, culminating with the highest domain in creativity, namely mysticism. [119]

Another, piquant point is Solov'ev's most vehement critique, in his encyclopaedia entry, that Hegel had applied dialectics to the absolute.
[120] On the one hand, from a theological perspective of history, he sought to preserve the absolute from being fully included in the historical process, and declared that 'it is impossible to admit that also absolute truth depends essentially on that process.' [121] On the other hand, in his early sophiological investigations, Solov'ev himself flirted with the same device of applying dialectics to Sophia and to the divine. [122]

A last difference is that, contrary to Hegel, he placed mysticism higher than philosophy. Even though Hegel's dialectics may be the most effective way of attaining truth logically, Solov'ev held that it does not reach absolute truth, which is grasped by mysticism.
It is in this sense perhaps that we can understand the following statement, dating from 1898:

Among the philosophers who approached truth, there is no one greater than Hegel. But the smallest among the philosophers who departed from truth itself, is greater than he is. [123]


The limitation of rational thought, which Solov'ev sensed as early as 1877, remained a constant statement. Solov'ev was opposed to Hegel making philosophy the adequate self-awareness of the absolute.

Solov'ev was attached to another category in Hegel linked to his dialectics, namely that of progress, but he did not as much grasp the tragic colour of Hegel's notion, according to which history marches forward by means of oppositions, conflicts, and contradictions.
[124] He rather picked up the content of the notion, which Hegel identified with the consciousness of freedom: 'World history, then, represents the phases in the development of the principle whose content is the consciousness of freedom.' [125] According to the principle that truth, in order to be actually true, must manifest itself concretely, Hegel posed the actualisation of freedom as ultimate goal: 'We have established Spirit's consciousness of freedom, and thereby the actualisation of this Freedom as the final purpose of the world.' [126] Solov'ev made a similar point and stated that history is about the realisation of all-unity through the awareness and concretisation of freedom. He agreed with Hegel that freedom is consciousness of the general goal and is the voluntary serving of that goal and that this was feasible only within the boundaries of powerful political rule. [127] At this point, two fundamental differences between the two thinkers arise. Firstly, while Hegel sustained that history marches forward irrespective of individual happiness, Solov'ev believed that the worth of the individual was increasingly respected in history and that he or she developed in more harmony with collectivity. Secondly, in contrast with Hegel's tendency to reduce God and transcendence into immanence, Solov'ev introduced a theology of history to reinforce the connection of history with transcendence.

Survey of world history

As far as the course of world history is concerned, strong analogies can be found in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija with the Hegelian system, all the more striking because Solov'ev wrote this text not knowing the Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte. A possible explanation of this is that Solov'ev received Hegel's scheme through his father, who had read Hegel's Vorlesungen. Both philosophers thought in terms of a succession of great civilisations by means of sublations. Here we can recognise the same civilisations as in Hegel's system, with the important difference that Hegel considered them thoroughly, and Solov'ev only superficially. For instance, Hegel included China and Japan in his survey of the Eastern civilisations, whereas Solov'ev limited himself to India in his work. A further parallel is that Christianity plays a central role in both systems, a point that is moreover related to theology of history. [128] The philosophy of history sketched in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija can be called the most Hegelian of all Solov'ev's surveys of history, in the sense that it provides tripartitions at all levels, encased within each other. Furthermore, the dynamics of these tripartitions arise and evolve by means or oppositions, negations, and sublations, which was also characteristic for Hegel's dialectical method.

However, two major differences with Hegel's survey appear. First, whilst for Hegel humanity is merely a goal and it is ultimately the Spirit, the idea, which is the main subject of history, Solov 'ev placed the emphasis on the living organism of the human community, which, in its ideal state, is the goal or the historical process. [129] This probably is a substantial difference between the two philosophers, nurtured by Solov'ev's eagerness to convince his readers, against Orthodox laissez-faire, that it was within the power of the human being to change reality. The emphasis that he placed on the living organism as the real subject of history can be understood in this context of his activism, which was absent in Hegel. There is a second, not less fundamental difference: whereas Hegel did not deal with the future at all, the future seemed to be the Russian philosopher's central focus of interest. [130] The absence of the future dimension was one of Solov'ev's fundamental reproaches of Hegel. In his eyes, the German philosopher had not left any space for further developments in the nineteenth century, such as socialism and the national movements, for instance in the Slavic countries. [131] While this is true, one can easily object to his criticism and show that Hegel had a conception of the future as a space that he did not fill in, as first having to have occurred before something rational can be said about it.

In addition to the above, Solov'ev applied dialectical schemes only to world history, not to Russian history, even within a single text that is dealing with both, Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija. [132] There, Russia represents the third element by which synthesis is possible between hostile forces, without itself being subjected to dialectical development. It remains unclear why Solov'ev did not interpret Russian history from the same dialectical prism as world history, unless it was for the very reason that Russia has an ultimate reconciling role to play; here Solov'ev leaves the philosophical register of history and enters the theological register. Significantly, in later surveys, Solov'ev disregarded the dialectical character of historical development and favoured a linear, organic interpretation of history. It thus seems that his flirt with Hegelian dialectics was a thing of youth and that their ways of thinking were in fact very different.

Historical actors:

Nations


The question of the exact influence of Hegel's conception of historical nations on Solov'ev cannot be definitively solved: it remains unclear whether it is a direct influence, an indirect one through his father, or simply an effect of the general way of thinking of the nineteenth century, Nevertheless, on the basis of Solov'ev's philosophy of history in Opravdanie dobra, parallels can be easily drawn with Hegel's Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, which strongly suggest that by that time Solov'ev had read them and had been inspired by them.

Roughly speaking, for Hegel, history is informed by the succession of four worlds [the Eastern, Greek, Roman, and Germanic Welten]. These are made up of nations or peoples [Volker], a term that Hegel used both in the broad sense of what we today would call 'civilisations' and in the narrow sense of 'peoples'. [133] The history of a nation in both senses consists first of a phase in which the nation develops self-consciousness and becomes aware of its mission. This national consciousness is a principle [Volksgeist] that is the manifestation or the Weltgeist at a certain moment of history. In a second phase, the nation performs its historical task. After that, it undergoes a phase of decline and fall, and is relayed by the appearance of a new principle, which is higher, and embedded in another nation. [134]

We find the main aspects of Hegel's conception in Solov'ev's meagre and schematic account of world history in Opravdanie dobra, where, quite in line with his time, he focused on nations in the narrow sense. In conformity with his time, he focussed on nations in the narrow sense. As it seems, he applied Hegel's views rather uncritically, and integrated them into his scheme of historical preparation for universal solidarity. The central aspects of his conception of historical nations are the following. Firstly, the idea of nationality appeared at a certain moment of history, narrated in the Old Testament, with the Jews, who were the first to develop a clear national consciousness. Correspondingly, they were the first to produce a philosophy of history. [135] Secondly, on the basis of this idea of nationality, groups physically formed a nation. [136] This condition is necessary in order to realise the good. Thirdly, the essence of this nation is not limited to its interest, on the contrary: it draws its meaning from its contribution to humanity. [137] Fourthly, not only do nations appear at a certain time, but their development is finite. [138] This is at least what Solov'ev implicitly suggested, without saying a word about the decay of nations. For instance, like Hegel, he no longer expected a new contribution from Europe. [139] Each of the West European nations (Italy, Spain, England, France, Germany) had enjoyed growth analogous to that of an individual, that is, childhood, youth, maturity, in which they had achieved inner unity and bloomed. Solov'ev observed that this development repeated itself for each nation, which in this way obeys a 'general ethico-historical law.' [140] Fourthly, this does not apply to all nations in the world. Some nations are active in history by a specific contribution to humanity by virtue of their national idea; others are not, and only the former are taken into account as historical nations. [141]

Solov'ev's conception of historical nations therefore echoes Hegel's theory. As far as the role of the state within the nation is concerned, Solov'ev evidenced a more critical distance.

State

In his articles for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, Solov'ev criticised the absolute character of the state in Hegel as a goal in itself. 'The state is the divine Idea as it exists on earth', Hegel had said. [142] Solov'ev concluded that 'Hegel even calls it [a] god.' [143] Indeed, for Hegel, the state was the most accomplished form of objective Spirit that history, or Reason has produced. In the form of its idea, and not of this or that particular state, the state is the final purpose of reason: 'the state in and by itself is the ethical whole, the actualisation of freedom; and it is the absolute end of reason that freedom should be actual.' [144] However, Solov'ev's criticism does not hold because it disregards the fact that in Hegel's system the state is the culmination point of the objective Spirit, not that of the absolute Spirit. [145]

Solov'ev refuted the exclusivity of the power of the state as stated by Hegel, as well as its status as a goal, using various arguments. We can regard Solov'ev's outspoken statements in Opravdanie dobra against the primacy of the state and the emphasis on a power shared at the top between the state, the church, and society, as a direct answer to Hegel's position. [146] He affirmed that the state was not an absolute form, but only an instrument, 'only the condition and the means of human progress, and it itself is gradually becoming more perfect in different respects.' [147] In the course of history, the state itself had improved according to Solov'ev, by 'gradually elevating its coercive power up to the height of moral authority.' [148] Contrary to what Solov'ev perhaps thought, Hegel would have subscribed to Solov'ev's statement that the state is subject to progress.

However, there are two significant similarities in Hegel and Solov'ev's conceptions of the state, which are overshadowed by Solov'ev's fierce criticism. These similarities, arguably, were conveyed to him through his father, the founding father of the state school of history, Sergej Solov'ev. Firstly, for Vladimir Solov'ev the state is a high form of development and a tool for historical progress. It is even the highest means available, at this stage of history, and the best channel for contributing to the realisation of the good. He encouraged the use of the material and spiritual forces of the state 'for the good of nations and the whole of humanity.' [149] Secondly, the state is the embodiment of morality in two ways. By its powers, it can guarantee the application of law, which is for Solov'ev the minimum level of morality. This point is exactly the same in Hegel: 'morals are a matter of the state and are handled by officials of the government and the courts.' [150] Besides, in the state morality becomes something that is thought about in the consciousness of its citizens and belongs to their self-consciousness. In this way, this self-consciousness receives a substantial content in the state. [151] On the whole, however, Solov'ev, who perhaps enjoyed more social and institutional independence than Hegel, went one step further, and did not hesitate to claim that institutions, and especially the state, should be reminded of their ideals. The duty of the individual 'would be to try and actively reform these institutions, insisting on what their function ought to be.' [152] Here we have the core of Solov'ev's motivation to intervene in Russian public life. He never condemned the institutions, the authorities as such, but indicated what they should do by reminding them of their role in history. [153] Hegel lived in a state of law [Rechsstaat], which despite its authoritarianism was the form of state that he believed in, whereas the Russian state in which Solov'ev lived was by far no state of law. This partly explains that the German philosopher committed himself less to reform than Solov'ev. On the whole, the latter permanently defended a normative, even moralistic position with respect to institutions, and notably the state, which was absent in Hegel, at least in his later years.

Great men

Although there is no textual evidence, one can suppose that by the mid-1880s, when he wrote various texts dealing with Peter I, Solov'ev was acquainted with Hegel's passage on great men in the Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte and borrowed it to depict the historical role of the tsar. The strong similarity of the notion in Hegel and in Solov'ev supports this hypothesis. [154] From the perspective of philosophy of history, he did not add any original elements to Hegel's category of heroes. But his category of prophets, which he developed in the theological and sophiological register of history, is an original addition to the Hegelian category of great men. Another hypothesis is that he assumed everything from his father, who was deeply inspired by Hegel when he wrote on Peter the Great.

Due to a direct or indirect influence, the category of great men is similar to Hegel's. These men are related to the divine in the sense that they are chosen and supported by Providence and then supported by it during their entire mission. In the society in which they live, they are the incarnation of a new consciousness. Solov'ev specified how such individuals arise from the masses of their fellow countrymen and which contribution they make to their environment. [155] He held that they were themselves not fully conscious of the goal that they were achieving. [156] On the one hand, this position seems identical to Hegel's characteristic of the role of the cunning of Reason in history, that is, in objective Spirit. On the other hand, it differs by its emphasis on the radical transcendence of God in the theological register of history, in contrast to Hegel's tendency to immanentise Reason in the objective Spirit. [157]

To summarise, two issues were raised at the start of this section, namely: To what extent can we speak of a Hegelian heritage in Solov'ev'? And to what extent is Solov'ev's conception of history a response to Hegel's philosophy of history, or an attempt to improve it?

As far as Solov'ev's Hegelian heritage in his historical views is concerned, the following results have been found. Firstly, we can speak of a direct influence that Solov'ev received on the overview of world history in dialectical terms in his early writings. He integrated the Hegelian categories of nations, state and great men acting upon history in a more complete way. With time, even though Solov'ev may have 'come to confess to Hegel more honestly and more openly', as Kline puts it, he also seemed to distance himself from Hegelian categories. This happens, for instance, with the Hegelian concept of process, of which Solov'ev made a merely linear process, and hereby lost the dialectical component of negation, which was central in Hegel. A close analysis which distinguishes the profound influence from superficial borrowings has revealed that Solov'ev did not totally apply this terminology in the Hegelian sense, for instance not to Russia, but was rather attracted by the wide scope of the Hegelian scheme. In this respect, Planty-Bonjour's conclusion of Solov'ev's remoteness from Hegel in spite of conceptual borrowings, seems to apply especially, though not exclusively, to Solov'ev's later works.

As far as Solov'ev's response to Hegel is concerned, there are two ways of expressing it, i.e. on the one hand a direct critique, and on the other, considerations included in his writings on history, which testify to his ambition to impose his own views by using reference frameworks other than Hegel's. Solov'ev formulated an explicit critique of Hegel's primacy given to the state vis-a-vis church and society, and, globally, the absence of a conception of the future. While the former criticism seems justified, the latter is a misunderstanding of Hegel's views. His response to Hegel is also essentially formulated by bringing to the fore meta-historical principles from different conceptions of history, namely what I have identified as theology of history and sophiology of history. The question arises whether Solov'ev challenged Hegel's philosophy of history. Perhaps he historicised the conception of the state more than Hegel did. The state is, after all, only a historical form of human organisation, which is subject to development and improvement. In contrast, Hegel's fascination with the state led him to make it an absolute end of historical development, in the sense that it could not be improved on or be completed by other institutions. Also, against the primacy of the Hegelian state, Solov'ev stressed the remaining distinction of the three powers, the state, the church and society.

An obvious difference of focus distinguishes the Hegelian from the Solov'evian philosophical approach of history. While Hegel identified the present as the most accomplished form of manifestation of the absolute for the time being, for Solov'ev, this phase still had to come in a near future; hence his concern for the future. This implied a difference of focus. Whilst Hegel focused on factual events in the past, Solov'ev, by situating the last and crucial period in an immediate future with respect to himself, allowed himself to play an active part in it in theory and in practice with his self-definition as a prophet -- a role Hegel did not assume. In other terms, Solov'ev rejected the idea of philosophy as Eule Minervas, and operated a shift to theosophy [see chap. II "Theology of History in Solov'ev'] and theurgy [see chap. IV 'Solov'ev's Sophiology of History']. In his eyes, history can be made and directed by man, in contrast to the fatalist taint of Hegel's view.

h) Sergej Solov'ev

i) Introduction


Sergej Solov'ev was the first author to offer a monumental and thorough history of Russia in his twenty-nine-volume History of Russia from the Oldest Times. [158] He was also, together with two other historians, the founding father of the Russian "state school" in the 1840s, which interpreted Russian history by emphasising the role of the state as the main factor of modernisation. This view played a major role in his philosophy of history, which he developed in historical works as well as in essays. [159] Vladimir Solov'ev familiarised himself with his father's work in his childhood and through it received a tremendous bulk of historical information as well as a historical worldview. One fact testifies to this transmission of knowledge: at the age of nineteen, Solov'ev assisted at the lectures given by his father on Peter the Great, and was given the task of writing them out. He rendered the content so well and so accurately that his father decided to use it for his university lectures. [160] So, even though Vladimir seemed as an adult not to have close contact with his father, and barely mentioned his works, he assimilated his father's work at an early age, which left its impression on his views on history. [161]

Solov'ev not only inherited a mass of historical facts and examples to serve his own theses from both the historian and the philosopher of history Sergej Solov'ev, but also, and most importantly, the interpretation of history as a universal progress, the organicistic model of development, the liberal filling of the categories East and West, the analysis of the origin and of the significance of the state in general, and the role of the individual, notably the hero Peter the Great. These issues are examined below in this order.

This analysis finds support in a number of thorough studies, including Joachim Sternkopf's comparative analysis between the historical views of Vladimir and Sergej Solov'ev -- the only comprehensive study on this issue -- as well as two recent publications on Sergej Solov'ev's philosophical views on history by Ol'ga Kazak and Ana Siljak. [162]

ii) Solov'ev's reception of Sergej Solov'ev's views on history

The young Vladimir received the view of history as a universal process from his first influence, his father. Sergej Solov'ev reflected within a universal framework, and sought to discover regularities [zakonomernosti], the most fundamental of which was the law of organic development applicable to the 'human organism as a whole.' [163] Although the expression in quotation marks seems to suggest that the historian applied the organicistic metaphor to humanity as a whole, a closer look at his works reveals that he applied it to the development of different nations only. [164] Vladimir as it were picked up the organicistic model naturally. [165] In contrast to his father, he extended it to humanity as a whole in order to describe the intrinsic bond existent in reality, or at least in principle, between peoples. However, he did not explicitly follow the organicistic parallel up to its logical conclusion that nations ultimately undergo aging, and die. Only as late as 1900 and in a weary tone did Solov'ev explicitly voice his father's view on the 'aged humanity', and the latter's conviction that humanity was a 'sick old man', and that world history had 'finished'. [166] Unchallenged by an optimistic view of human progress, this view interestingly gives full priority to a biological view of humanity drawn to its tragic conclusion: humanity was on the point of dying of old age.

However, both thinkers conceived of humanity not only as a unified entity or organism, but also as a being split into two antagonistic civilisations, East and West: in the Hegelian and occidentalist view, the East was conservative, while the forces of progress lay in the West. Whereas Sergej Solov'ev always displayed a univocally pro-European stance, this became Solov'ev's general position only at the end of the 1880s, after he had abandoned Slavophile anti-Europeanism. In his early years, by contrast, Solov'ev addressed a fierce criticism to individualistic and materialistic Europe, and until his death, never ceased to defend a view of the state that could overcome the limitedness of the Western state. Nevertheless, there is probably a line of continuity between Sergej and Vladimir Solov'ev on this point. Sergej emphasised the spiritual nature of both civilizations in a descriptive and historical way. Even if he was concerned with pointing to the differences in a political and cultural respect, we can assume that his investigations of the East-West opposition provided the more liberal-oriented Vladimir with a confirmation of his own hypotheses and with the opportunity to elaborate on this conflict from the teleological perspective, that is, by indicating its resolution.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 1:19 am

Part 3 of 4

From clan to state

Regarding the inner development from clan to state, it appears that Solov'ev for the most part embraced his father's argumentation, which in turn echoed Hegel's interpretation of the origin of the state in the patriarchal order. In his treatment of the life of peoples and the rise of nations, Solov'ev used the same genealogy and terminology as his father, which strongly suggests that he was inspired by him directly, and not by Hegel on this issue. The first form of community was the clan, followed by the militia [druziny], the first political unions, Eastern monarchies, and finally the state. [167] This formal, external process was accompanied and strengthened by the inner, substantial development of the national character. [168]

Both Sergej and Vladimir placed particular emphasis on communal life as a natural dimension of human life. Sergej Solov'ev, and Vladimir in his trail, identified the origin of historical development with clan life. Clan life, in the long run, had hindered the blooming of the individual, and had incited gifted individuals to leave it and form militias. However, clan life, even if it was due to disappear, had contributed to the formation of a historical person in the figure of its leader, who determined the formation of the character of a people, or, in other words, its national principles. On this point, Vladimir Solov'ev explicitly referred to Sergej Solov'ev. [169] Once militias were formed, these began to form alliances, which gave birth to political unions. Separate peoples emerged, which subsequently formed the first states, the Eastern monarchies. [170] Solov'ev took up his father's research and interpreted these monarchies as a necessary stage in the preparation of world solidarity. [171] He also, and quite exceptionally, made efforts to bring together speculative views and historical facts. When dealing with Eastern monarchies and military-theocratic despotism, he used recently discovered inscriptions of Assyrian and Persian kings as sources. [172]

It is impossible that such governments as have hitherto existed in the world, could have commenced by any other means than a total violation of every principle sacred and moral. The obscurity in which the origin of all the present old governments is buried, implies the iniquity and disgrace with which they began. The origin of the present government of America and France will ever be remembered, because it is honourable to record it; but with respect to the rest, even Flattery has consigned them to the tomb of time, without an inscription.

It could have been no difficult thing in the early and solitary ages of the world, while the chief employment of men was that of attending flocks and herds, for a banditti of ruffians to overrun a country, and lay it under contributions. Their power being thus established, the chief of the band contrived to lose the name of Robber in that of Monarch; and hence the origin of Monarchy and Kings.

The origin of the Government of England, so far as relates to what is called its line of monarchy, being one of the latest, is perhaps the best recorded. The hatred which the Norman invasion and tyranny begat, must have been deeply rooted in the nation, to have outlived the contrivance to obliterate it. Though not a courtier will talk of the curfew-bell, not a village in England has forgotten it.

Those bands of robbers having parcelled out the world, and divided it into dominions, began, as is naturally the case, to quarrel with each other. What at first was obtained by violence was considered by others as lawful to be taken, and a second plunderer succeeded the first. They alternately invaded the dominions which each had assigned to himself, and the brutality with which they treated each other explains the original character of monarchy. It was ruffian torturing ruffian. The conqueror considered the conquered, not as his prisoner, but his property. He led him in triumph rattling in chains, and doomed him, at pleasure, to slavery or death. As time obliterated the history of their beginning, their successors assumed new appearances, to cut off the entail of their disgrace, but their principles and objects remained the same. What at first was plunder, assumed the softer name of revenue; and the power originally usurped, they affected to inherit.

From such beginning of governments, what could be expected but a continued system of war and extortion? It has established itself into a trade. The vice is not peculiar to one more than to another, but is the common principle of all. There does not exist within such governments sufficient stamina whereon to engraft reformation; and the shortest and most effectual remedy is to begin anew on the ground of the nation.

What scenes of horror, what perfection of iniquity, present themselves in contemplating the character and reviewing the history of such governments! If we would delineate human nature with a baseness of heart and hypocrisy of countenance that reflection would shudder at and humanity disown, it is kings, courts and cabinets that must sit for the portrait. Man, naturally as he is, with all his faults about him, is not up to the character.

Can we possibly suppose that if governments had originated in a right principle, and had not an interest in pursuing a wrong one, the world could have been in the wretched and quarrelsome condition we have seen it? What inducement has the farmer, while following the plough, to lay aside his peaceful pursuit, and go to war with the farmer of another country? or what inducement has the manufacturer? What is dominion to them, or to any class of men in a nation? Does it add an acre to any man's estate, or raise its value? Are not conquest and defeat each of the same price, and taxes the never-failing consequence? -- Though this reasoning may be good to a nation, it is not so to a government. War is the Pharo-table of governments, and nations the dupes of the game.

If there is anything to wonder at in this miserable scene of governments more than might be expected, it is the progress which the peaceful arts of agriculture, manufacture and commerce have made beneath such a long accumulating load of discouragement and oppression. It serves to show that instinct in animals does not act with stronger impulse than the principles of society and civilisation operate in man. Under all discouragements, he pursues his object, and yields to nothing but impossibilities.

-- Thomas Paine, "The Rights of Man"


The view that the state was the culminating point of the evolution of human organisation was clearly borrowed from Sergej Solov'ev. The historian identified the rise of the state in both the narrow and the broad sense with the appearance of a new order. The state fostered solidarity, introduced the distinction between public and private, and favoured aspects which fed spiritual life, such as religion, science and art. Solov'ev assimilated these views. [173] He valued the state in the broad sense foremost for its totalising character. In his eyes, the state is the collective organisation that embraces all others, and by virtue of which, demands the participation of everybody to its action. [174] The originality of Solov'ev's interpretation of the state in comparison with his father lies in the link between state and morality. [175] In this sense, Solov'ev showed himself more Hegelian than his father.

Sergej Solov'ev also devoted attention to the development of the Russian state in the narrow sense. [176] Russia had to move beyond both the clan principle of hierarchy and central power (typical for Asia) and the militia principle of diversity and autonomy (typical for Europe). This was possible only by developing 'the "state [pravitel'stvennyj] principle" of government and the "civic" form of social structure.' [177] The former is related specifically to state in the narrow sense. The historian investigated the development of a Russian Rechtsstaat [pravovoe gosudarstvo]. Solov'ev also devoted analyses to the role of the state in the narrow sense. [178] He defined it as a 'social body with a definite organisation, containing in itself the fullness of positive rights of the one supreme authority.' [179] He examined the function of state as warrant of the law and as 'embodied law.' [180] Law must rest upon a real power in order that its aspects, its public character, its concreteness, and its actual application can be carried out. [181]

Solov'ev therefore defended a statist view, which he most probably inherited directly from his father, while going philosophically further than he did, and thereby getting closer to Hegel. Characteristically, while his father limited himself, quite logically for a historian, to the empirical form of the phenomenon of the state, the son elaborated a normative determination of the tasks of society, such as a consolidation of the state order, the repression of individualism, and the ethical significance of concrete phenomena. For instance, concerning the abolition of serfdom in Russia (1861), he identified three stages, first a moral preparation in educated society, second the issuing of a law by the state, and third, a higher consciousness among the majority of the population as a consequence. In this case, the 'sudden progress is solely due to the tact that the organised social force [the state, MC] was inspired by moral demands and transformed them into an objective law of life.' [182] Here Solov'ev wanted to emphasise the crucial role of the state in making morality objective in law, which was visible, clear, and objectively known, and so making it an obligation for all. [183]

The individual

Both thinkers dealt with the role of individuals in history along two lines. Firstly, they discussed individual freedom in the state. Both Sergej and Vladimir Solov'ev examined the opposition between the private and the public domain, both emphasised the goal that the forms of community serve, rather than the individual implications, and both postulated that the individual shared the same nature with community, in conformity with their use of the organicistic metaphor. [184] However, there was a distinction between individual and community that was made possible only within the state, namely the distinction between public and private. Sergej Solov'ev defended individuality against the state, an attitude that Solov'ev shared. [185]

Secondly, outstanding individuals in a community, or heroes, were the object of special investigation by Sergej Solov'ev. His son adopted the analysis of Peter the Great made by his father along a Hegelian line. [186] Against a current mythologizing interpretation of Peter the Great, the historian examined the historical role of this figure in a rather pragmatic manner. Peter's tremendous reformatory action was the result of the whole prior history of Russia. [187] He was the representative of the people, and fulfilled their needs in a given period of time. He was the leader, but not the creator of the new orientation of Russia towards Europe. Solov'ev assumed Sergej Solov'ev's treatment of Peter the Great in its entirety. [188] The activity of car' bogatyr' Peter the Great was so determinant that it formed the 'centre' of Russian history, dividing it in two, one preceding his reign, the other following it. His reign had been anticipated in the call to the Varangians, and was in particular the direct result of the two preceding centuries of Russian history. Concerning the era of Peter, where Sergej Solov'ev meticulously analysed the issue of the numerous reforms, which touched upon education, law, administration, culture, religion, army, clothing and others, Vladimir Solov'ev only provided general statements on the Christian significance of his work, hereby switching to the theological register of history. [189] In a more detailed investigation, he explicitly quoted his father's argumentation regarding the reform of the clergy. [190] From a global perspective, both thinkers interpreted the reign of Peter the Great as the entry of the Russian nation into world history. [191] This entry had been achieved not only by transformations of Russian society and institutions, but also by fostering international relationships, and by imposing Russia as a nation a part entiere on the strategic map of Europe. Sergej Solov'ev particularly emphasised Peter's historic achievements of instituting the significance of the state, generating among Russians a sense of citizenship [grazdanstvennost'], and issuing laws protecting the individual. Vladimir in particular used this last point and interpreted it from the ethical perspective by arguing that the tsar had succeeded in reintegrating the Christian principles into society and politics. [192]

In summary, Solov'ev was significantly inspired by Sergej Solov'ev's work and assumed many categories, arguments, and concepts that governed his father's discourse on history, namely the concept of organic development, the liberal interpretation of the opposition East-West, the genealogy of the state, and the figure of Peter the Great. This influence was prior to those of Hegel and Comte, and left a deep impression on Solov'ev. This did not stop him from rearranging them in his thoroughly teleological view, hereby falling into teleological determinism -- a position Sergej Solov'ev rejected, along with a purely speculative approach of history, because it neglected empirical reality. [193]

c) Comte

i) Introduction


The father of positivism, Auguste Comte, had succeeded in establishing an entirely immanent philosophy of history, which substituted Hegel's primacy of philosophy with that of science, thus discarding the elements of transcendence in Hegel, and promised the triumph of positive science in creating the conditions for a happy society. Solov'ev devoted a great deal of effort to criticizing the philosophical school of positivism, which was pervasive in his time throughout all fields of human and natural sciences in Russia. His primary approach to Comte was resolutely critical, as the title of his dissertation, Crisis of Western Philosophy; Against the Positivists, shows. [194] Arguably, Solov'ev's primary critical approach was motivated by a perception of Comte as a competitor in the same field. He dealt with Comte's views related to history in three main texts. Firstly, in the appendix to his dissertation he directed his criticism at Comte's law of three stages. Then, in the 1890s, he wrote the entry 'Kont' for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, devoted to the life and teaching of the French thinker. Finally, in a public lecture in 1898, he commemorated the century of the birth of Comte and took another perspective in order to 'pay [his] old debt towards the old thinker.' [195]

Until very recently, the question of Comte's influence on Solov'ev's views on history has been massively overlooked. One reason is the absence of thorough studies of the reception of Comte in Russia, despite his success in the 1860s-1870s, which was comparable to that of Hegel two decades earlier. [196] Another reason, more specific to the reception of Comte in Solov'ev, is the sort of blind belief, based on Solov'ev's own highly critical statements, that he was entirely opposed to the system of the French thinker. [197] Yaclav Zdenek David was the first scholar who examined the issue thoroughly and concluded to a direct influence of Comte on Solov'ev. [198] After him, the only serious contribution comes from S.B. Rocinskij, who has provided a detailed account of Solov'ev's views on Comte. [199]

Solov'ev showed a sustained interest with respect to positivism in general, and Auguste Comte in particular, from the very beginning of his philosophical training. He had a thorough knowledge of Comte's two chief works, Cours de philosophie positive, and Systeme de politique positive. The sharpness of his criticism could not conceal the significance he attached to positivism as well as the affinity he bore with Comte. [200] His relationship to the French philosopher can therefore be characterised as, on the one hand, originating in sharp criticism, which was preserved in the 1890s, though blended and more balanced. On the other hand, Solov'ev had a close affinity with some aspects of Comte's philosophy, which he grew to admit and value. This two-fold attitude also shapes his reaction to Comte's views on history. In this connection, two questions have to be addressed, about the hypothetical Comtianism of his philosophy of history and about the soundness of his criticism of Comte's views. My thesis is, firstly, that only in his early work, Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, can one detect a Comtian scheme of history; secondly, that Solov'ev's criticism of Comte's positivism and of his law of the three stages was not entirely consistent. Below, I investigate the place in Solov'ev's work of the Comtian law of the three stages, his concept of progress, and his concept of humanity as a historical subject. In doing so, I will show the partial influence on Solov'ev with respect to the first point, a direct influence on the second point, and an affinity between the two philosophers on the third.

ii) Solov'ev 's reception of Comte's views on history

The law of the three stages


The question of Solov'ev's reception of the Comtian law of three stages cannot be entirely solved, for reasons explained below. However, it is possible to draw a few hypothetical conclusions.

Comte's law of the three stages can be described in brief as follows: history is governed by a process that consists of three subsequent stages, namely the theological, the metaphysical, and the positive stage. [201] In the theological stage, which lasted from Ancient times to the Middle Ages, man searched for the ultimate cause of all things in supra-natural beings (in fetishism, veneration of the stars, polytheism and monotheism), in the metaphysical stage he substituted these by abstract concepts (in speculative thought, notably ontology). With the foundation of positivism, a substitution took place of the unreachable search for causes, typical for the theological and the metaphysical stage, by the simple search for laws, i.e. constant relationships between observed phenomena. In doing so, humanity had entered its final and most advanced phase of development, which was bound to overcome the limitations of the two previous ones, and to have universal application. This application would first take place in the field of knowledge, and then, notably on the basis of the new science, sociology, would be extended to society and politics, resulting in the establishment of a fair and stable order for all. [202] Comte illustrated this scheme with examples from the history of thought, mainly religion, philosophy, and science.

Solov'ev's first reaction was a total rejection of this theory, which, in his eyes, sought to suppress knowledge of the absolute. [203] In the appendix to his dissertation, he provided two arguments to demonstrate the inconsistency of Comte's theory of the three stages. Firstly, Comte did not understand what theology and philosophy properly speaking were. [204] In my eyes, this argument is partially valid. Solov'ev was right to the extent that Comte often provided only a caricature of theological and metaphysical preoccupations. [205] But these schematic definitions contained some relevant points, with which Solov'ev himself would agree; [206] as the Russian philosopher himself admitted, the previous metaphysical systems had failed in attaining true knowledge by looking for an object external to the subject. [207] Secondly, he affirmed that the succession of theology, metaphysics and positive science was inconsistent because these fields and methods were incompatible. This argument would be sound only if Comte had identified the theological stage with theology, the metaphysical stage with metaphysics, and the positive stage with science. However, a closer look at Comte's text shows that despite his schematism, he did not take this step. Rather, he defined these phases far more generally, as ways of thinking, 'different theoretical stages', which were operative in 'each branch of our knowledge.' [208] So Solov'ev's critique, according to which these two flaws ruined the positivists' ambition of a universal system, does not hold.

Two decades later, in the article for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, Solov'ev adopted a different approach. Ironically, Comte, in his own intellectual development, had submitted himself to this law of development, but in the opposite direction. He had grown from a positive, scientific view through the metaphysic principle and arrived at the theological stage. [209] Comte's error had thus been to think that this process happens only in one direction, in contrast to that which he demonstrated in his own life. In fact, Solov'ev argued, this process took place in both directions, not only once, but several times, and until 1500. Moreover, Comte did not -- and could not, one should add -- take into account a new phenomenon, namely the new interest in metaphysical and religious-mystical questions that followed positivism. [210] These arguments against the unilinearity of the law are coherent, although the relationships between the Comtian stages are more flexible than a strict succession from the one to the other. [211] One could also address the same criticism to Solov'ev himself: he also did not take much account of the possibility of a revival of a principle which was opposed to his ideals, for instance political separatism.

Nevertheless, Solov'ev saw some truth in the law of the three stages:

Any idea which has historical significance originally appears as the expression of an immediate certitude (intuition, inspiration, which corresponds to the theological stage of Comte): it then becomes the object of abstract thought (Comte's metaphysical stage), and eventually is posed as the task of a real realisation or incarnation (Comte's positive stage). Understood in this way, the law of the three stages would really have a universal application, as one of the main variations of the logical formula of all progress, established by Hegel. [212]


Cornte had discovered a universal law applicable to ideas. In my opinion, however, the difference between Comte and Hegel is more substantial than Solov'ev thought. The similarities between Hegel and Comte are the triadic constructions and the continuous ascending line of progress shaping history. But the divergences are perhaps even more important. The fundamentally original aspect of the Hegelian dialectical development, negation, or conflict, was not operative in a structural way in the Comtian organic conception of development. Solov'ev's abusive identification of the Hegelian dialectics with organic development [as I have pointed to in 2a], led him to associate Hegel too closely with Comte.

What did Solov'ev do with the law of the three stages? Did he borrow it, rework it, or suggest an alternative scheme? This question cannot be solved with certainty. Some elements certainly suggest borrowing. For example, even though Solov'ev criticised some of the conclusions drawn by Comte, he nevertheless reflected on the basis of similar principles. [213] Solov'ev, like Comte, distinguished three types of knowledge, namely theology, philosophy, and science, which he identified as absolute, formal, and material degrees [stepeni], an equivalent term for the Comtian states or stages [etats]. Also similar to Comte is the distinction of three main areas of human activity: intellectual, social, and aesthetic or creative. Solov'ev, like Comte, related manifestations of the three stages to the three areas of human activity: the absolute, or theology and the ecclesiastical institution, the formal, or metaphysics and the political institutions, and the material, or natural science and economic institutions. However, Solov'ev distanced himself from Comte in his application of the stages to the domain of aesthetics, which he approached from a sophiological perspective. Therefore, only the intellectual and social areas are examined in this account.

It seems that Solov'ev consistently applied the Comtian law of the three stages in his survey of world history in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija. [214] The first phase in history was dominated by the absolute principle, similarly to Comte's definition of the first stage as theological. In this stage, religion governed all areas of human activity, which were not differentiated. After Jesus Christ, a struggle occurred, mostly in Western history, between the absolute, the formal, and the material, in all domains of human activity. In the Middle Ages, the conflict between the absolute and the formal could again be found in the struggle between theology and philosophy, and between church and state. From the end of the Middle Ages up to the French revolution, Solov'ev saw the victory of the formal over the absolute in the form of the domination of the state over the church, and of metaphysics over theology. The first victory of the material stage could be seen in the ascendance of science and in the rise of the third estate and of industry. However, while Comte positively valued the French revolution, the boom of industrialisation, and the triumph of science as the definitive 'success of the positive spirit', Solov'ev regarded them as only a temporary phase. But they agreed on the necessity of a last phase to overcome the antagonisms between the three principles.

However, an important obstacle to the conclusion that Solov'ev simply assumed the entire Comtian scheme is that some points are present in other philosophical systems. The distinction between philosophy, theology and science is not specifically Comtian. More importantly, a law of the three stages can be found in other theories, such as those about the state of nature (Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau drew a scheme of i) the state of nature, ii) the fall, and iii) a new order). Also Hegel pointed out three phases of development, namely confusion, distinction, new unity. The question therefore arises whether Solov'ev took these elements from other theories, from Hegel or from Comte (both directly or through Sergej Solov'ev). If we focus on the two philosophers discussed in this chapter, Hegel and Comte, the following hypotheses can be formulated. On the one hand, the fact that, at the time when he wrote Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, he was acquainted with Comte's three stages theory, and not with Hegel's philosophy of history, suggests that he borrowed the scheme from Comte. On the other hand, the logic adapted in the survey of history is rather dialectic, as the central role given to conflicts, oppositions, and negations, however mechanic they seem, suggests. Solov'ev possibly picked up Comte's concept of the three stages, and related these stages to each other by means of Hegelian dialectics. [215]

A far more obvious influence can be detected in Solov'ev's borrowing of the Comtian definition of progress in terms of order. [216] Solov'ev's formula that 'true progress is the progress of order', is strikingly similar to those of Comte: [217] 'for the new philosophy order permanently forms the necessary condition of order; and reciprocally, progress becomes the necessary goal of order.' [218] There is no textual evidence that Solov'ev had read this passage by Comte; however, Comte's famous slogan of positivism 'Love as a principle, and order as a basis; progress as a goal', must have been widely known. [219]

The concept of humanity

To the concept of humanity, which was central in Comte's second system, Solov'ev devoted two texts, namely his article for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia and his lecture commemorating the hundredth anniversary of Comte's birth, eloquently entitled 'The Idea of Humanity in Auguste Comte.' Solov'ev pointed out four characteristics of humanity in Comte, which belong to a specifically philosophical perspective on history. [220] The Russian philosopher was eager to establish the reality of humanity against the refutation of its existence by thinkers such as Danilevskij, and, clearly, found support in Comte's texts. [221]

Firstly, humanity can be divided into groups, such as family and fatherland, as Comte pointed out, but it is in its essence indivisible, and is more than the totality of its components. [222] Secondly, humanity has more plenitude than smaller groups, such as family and fatherland, and its components have no meaning when taken in isolation. To make this point, Solov'ev referred to Comte's analogy between sociology and geometry, which shows the relationship between the whole and the parts. Here Solov'ev reproduced Comte's following argument: the dot can be identified with a person, the line with family (semejstvo), surface with people, the tri-dimensional figure with a race, and the full physical body with humanity: taken separately, these parts are only abstract. [223] The third aspect of humanity follows from this analogy: the essence of humanity is prior to the essence of its components. This priority of order is demonstrated by the general movement of world history. Or, in Solov'ev terms, who referred to Comte:

A body is not formed of dots, lines, figures, but is already presupposed by them: humanity is not formed of persons, families, peoples, but is presupposed by them. Of course we see that in the general course of world history these isolated and collective elements of human life draw nearer and nearer to each other and seem to shape themselves together, but with this they do not create humanity in its essence, since it is already presupposed in this unifying movement itself, as its necessary basis, incitation [pobuzdenie] and leadership. [224]


“Dots, Lines, Triangles, Cubes, Circles” and finally “Spheres” — why or how? Because, says the Commentary, such is the first law of Nature, and because Nature geometrizes universally in all her manifestations: “The Mother is the fiery Fish of Life. She scatters her spawn and the Breath heats and quickens it. The grains are soon attracted to each other and form the curds in the Ocean. The larger lumps coalesce and receive new spawn, in fiery dots, triangles and cubes which ripen, and at the appointed time some of the lumps detach themselves and assume spheroidal form. Motion becomes the whirlwind and sets them into rotation."

-- The Secret Doctrine -- The Synthesis of Science, Religion, and Philosophy, by Helena Petrovna Blavatsky


Rather than infer an influence of Comte on Solov'ev's concept of humanity, it seems that Solov'ev only assumed the analogy between sociology and geometry as a useful metaphor for his own conception of humanity. A look at the central place occupied by this concept in the whole work of Solov'ev suffices to demonstrate that the Russian philosopher did not have to borrow it from Comte, but arrived at the same definition and significance of humanity. [225]

Solov'ev's conception of history bore affinity with that of Comte in four respects. Firstly, they shared a conception of history as being mainly the history of ideas, of intellectual development. Secondly, they believed in the reality of humanity as the ultimate entity, thereby providing human groups with a meaning. Thirdly, both presented a tripartition of history into an initial, transitory, and final stage. Fourthly, and more generally, both were oriented towards the future as the dimension in which ideal society would be fully implemented. In this respect, both viewed their own contribution as crucial. Their focus on the future also explains the hasty, schematic treatment to which they submitted history. More specifically, the question of Solov'ev's borrowing the Comtian law of three stages can be partially solved. It seems that Solov'ev did borrow some schemes, but one should bear in mind that these schemes also contain Hegelian elements. The question of who exerted a more decisive influence cannot be easily answered. Only the definition of progress in necessary combination with order bears an incontestably Comtian stamp. As far as the Comtian concept of humanity is concerned, this is perhaps the point on which Solov'ev admired Comte most. However, he himself arrived at the same definition of this category and only found additional support in Comte's formulations and analogies. In doing so he showed his admiration for the scientific approach of the French thinker. After all, as we read in an early letter [see introduction II], it was part of his youth dream to fully acknowledge the role of science and to integrate its most fundamental results in a synthesis with philosophy and religion.

Conclusion

History in its immanent development deserved attention and respect in its own right. This motivated Solov'ev to elaborate a view based on some key points made in 19th century philosophy of history, namely: an acknowledgement of one universal goal-oriented process achieved mainly by humanity, which in a harmonious unity contains smaller entities, the nations. These, in their turn, are guided by world historical heroes, who introduce novelty in an established order. Solov'ev assimilated these points and reorganised them on the basis of his chief metaphysical principle of all-unity. The originality of Solov'ev's philosophical register of history lies mostly in his constant attempt to provide historical events with a universal meaning. This was the first time such an approach has been applied to Russian history as a whole, future included.

For this purpose, he drew aspects from Comte, Hegel, and for the larger part from Sergej Solov'ev. As a matter of fact, Solov'ev's reception of Hegel's, Comte's, and Sergej Solov'ev's philosophy of history is an interesting case of his extremely differentiated way of dealing with philosophical schools. In Solov'ev's work, reception took the form of a fully assimilated legacy (his father's world view and categories of historical actors), affinities which he acknowledged (with Comte's conception of humanity), or which he rejected (the schematism of Comte's law of the three stages), a criticism combined with approval (Hegel's conception of the state), a misinterpretation and unacknowledged distancing (Hegelian dialectics), up to a total rejection (the epistemological foundation of Comte's positivism). This wide range of reactions explains the complexity of the issue of the reception of history in Solov'ev's thought.

In a global assessment, one must conclude that Solov'ev did not develop a consistent philosophy of history for two main reasons. Firstly, the philosopher was often not specific enough in his treatment of history and too speculative, and as a result of an insufficient 'data base' he failed to provide an articulate interpretation in this register. This relates to his main focus on the teleological principle of all-unity, which led him to simplifications in order to make history result in the pre-defined ideal. Secondly, there are conflicting schemes, such as his dialectical treatment of world history and his linear treatment of Russian history. Solov'ev ultimately privileged a linear and organic concept of development to Hegelian dialectics. But in order to be convincing, this shift of position should have been accompanied by a criticism of the inconsistency of dialectics when applied to history.

One can say that Solov'ev criticised philosophies of history as much as they inspired him. The rationalistic and positivist interpretation of history provided by Hegel and Comte respectively, which, in his eyes, implies that there is ultimately nothing outside history, could only meet with resistance from Solov'ev's part. He used the theological register of history to firmly establish against these two thinkers the transcendence of God and the unconditional character of the good. In this respect, he showed himself at ease in his criticism of the Comtian system, which he could easily refute because of the philosophical schematism and to some extent superficiality inherent to the French scholar. Interestingly, he neglected the theological components of Hegel's views on history, and hereby, whether consciously or not, reduced them to a 'pure', that is, immanent, philosophy of history. By overlooking Hegel's developments of the absolute Spirit, he reduced the latter's position to a 'theory of the objective Spirit.' Perhaps this reduction made it easier for him to react to the German philosopher from a theological and sophiological perspective.

There were fundamental limitations in philosophy of history, which Solov'ev could not accept. God as main though transcendent actor was neglected or even removed, as well as the absolute value of the good. Besides, in the Comtian system, ideal society seemed realisable by human hands alone. Religion and the church were relegated to one of the many pillars of mental and social life, or removed from the social ideal. Pure immanence vs. the primacy of God's transcendence, human vs. divine agency, evolution vs. creation, reason vs. faith: philosophy of history and theology of history seemed impossible to combine within one system. Like Hegel, Solov'ev sought a way to bridge this gap. Unlike the German philosopher, he found it in sophiology of history.

_______________

Notes:

1. Opravdanie dobra, p. 473, transl. p. 396.

2. Van der Zweerde 2001 p. 232.

3. He established the category of such a goal a priori, justifying it only by the fact that our consciousness demands a 'general and ultimate goal" (Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, p. 185).

4. Ibid., pp.186-187.

5. Ibid., p. 215. The term 'all-unity' appeared later in Solov'ev's work [see footnote 6].

6. See the definition of all-unity: 'I call true or positive all-unity that in which one [edinoe] exists not on account of everyone or to their detriment, but to the benefit of all' ('Pervyj sag k polozitel'noj estetike'. S. 1991. pp. 90-98: p. 95 n. English translation in Wozniuk 2003, 'A First Step toward a Positive Aesthetic', pp. 135-143: p. 140); 'in the second, positive sense, the relationship of the one principle to all is understood as the relationship of the all-encompassing spiritual-organic whole to the living members and elements that find themselves in it' ('Vseedinstvo', SS. 12. p. 231).

7. In theory, it is inaccessible because one cannot have a concept of the ultimate state of things. In this sense, this 'limit' may be only conceptually 'ideal', but in reality history is moving towards it ('Pervyj sag k polozitci'noj estetike', pp. 92-93).

8. Ibid., p. 95.

9. The cyclical elements [see subsections 1eii and 2b] and dialectical [see subsection 2a] are present in Solov'ev's work, but play a secondary role.

10. Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, p. 187.

11. See for instance 'Rukoyodjascie mysli "Istoriceskogo Obozrenija'" (SS. 6, pp. 363-373: p. 370). This statement unmistakably leads to tensions with the TH scheme, which Solov'ev did not solve. According to the theological scheme of history, there is n strict separation between nature and man. Contrary to Kant, who distinguished between the finalised activity of the intellect [Zwecktatigkeit] and the finalised effectiveness of nature [Zweckmassigkeit], Solov'ev made both terms equivalent and elevated them to a general category applicable to the world (Sternkopf 1973, pp. 82. 161). Solov'ev developed the substantial unity between man and nature as a central aspect of his sophiology of history [see chap. IV]. On the one hand, for Solov'ev society has all the features of an organism. On the other, society is an organism sui generis, thus is differentiated from a biological organism, but on this point Solov'ev did not specify in which sense. In another discussion, he agreed with Darwin that the fundamental factor distinguishing man from animal is the fact that man possesses moral feeling (Opravdanie dobra, p. 26).

12. The significance of the natural sciences in his thought, in particular the theory of evolution, should be emphasised. In a letter dated 1873, he wrote: 'one has to appropriate oneself the general results of the scientific development' (Pis 'ma 3. p. 89). Solov'ev is one of the very few Orthodox authors who took into account the theme of evolution (Olivier Clement, 'Vladimir Soloviev, theologien de la modernite?', Contacts 169 (1995), pp. 35-45).

13. From this perspective, the use of the organicistic metaphor allowed Solov'ev to argue that the social forms influence the individual, and so permits him to counter the attitude of people like Lavrov, Mikhailovksij, and Tolstoj who neglected history as the collective shaping of the world, and worked towards the good only on an individual basis.

14. This discrepancy between an aspired universality and an adopted eurocentrism is typical for most nineteenth-century philosophers.

15. See Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, pp. 197-216 for the account that follows. Concerning the question of a Hegelian influence on the terminology, see below, subsection 2b): concerning the question of the law of the three stages from Comte being borrowed, see subsection 2c).

16. More ancient civilisations such as Egypt and China are not mentioned.

17. Solov'ev stated the same phenomenon in the field of science, where positivism became dominant, and in art, with 'utilitarian realism' (Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, pp. 205-208).

18. There also he pointed to three main periods, without, however, providing historical data. This second account is characterised by a strict continuity between the stages, which stands in sharp contrast with the first periodisation made by means of conflicts between the phases and between their composing elements.

19. About the Varangians and Peter, see 'O narodnosti i narodnykh delakh v Rossii', Nacional'nyj vopros I, S. 1989 I , pp. 279-293: p. 285. Another version of this scheme was the following. First of all, there was a political emancipation, with the rejection of Tatar and Lithuanian power, an inner, economical emancipation, i.e. of peasants from serfdom in 1863, and finally a spiritual emancipation, which still had to come ('Kogda byl ostavlen russkij put' i kak k nemu vernut'sja? (Po povodu "Zametki O vnutrennem sostojanii Rossii" K.S. Aksakova)', Nase Nasledie, 1988, 2, pp. 81-84). Solov'ev recurrently presented this scheme of Russian history in his publicistika, especially in relation to actual problems [see case studies].

20. 'Vremja' (SS. 10. pp. 230-231).

21. Worth mentioning are five aphorisms about time that Solov'ev wrote in a style and tone closer to his poetry than to his philosophical works, and, as pointed out, can be associated to the humoristic aphorisms of his contemporary writer Koz'ma Prutkov. See his 'Mysli o vremeni', published for the first time by I.G. Visneveckij, 'Vladimir Solov'ev kak estestvennyj myslitel'', Aequinox MCMXCIII (Moskva: Kniznyj sad, 1993), pp. 230-235: p. 234. One example: 'It has been noticed a long time ago that there are three times: the past, the present, and the future, but it is not yet known whether there is a fourth one' (Ibid., p. 234).

22. Lemma 'Kant' for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia (SS. 10, pp. 345-380), p. 377.

23. Opravdanie dobra, p. 338.

24. The definition of optimism which he gave in the entry 'Optimizm' for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia applies to him as well: 'view according to which the existing world is the best possible one and all that accomplishes itself in it leads to the good' (5S. 9, p. 250).

25. Arguably, it is his attachment to tradition that explains why many of his views were, even in his days, considered conservative; for instance, he did not question the Russian tsarist regime as an institution. On the other hand, he could just as well be considered a utopian on the basis of his numerous statements on the ideal universal community that had to be built.

26. 'Ponjatie o Boge', p. 25.

27. 'Pervyj sag k polozitel'noj estetike', p. 93, transl. p. 139 [italics Solov'ev's].

28. Solov'ev did not specify whether this goal could be attained by man alone, or whether the intervention of God was necessary. One can assume that, in order to be consistent with his theological scheme, he admitted that this goal, once realised. would mean the end of history.

29. On this point, one could logically object that it is possible to conceive of an infinite progress towards a precise goal that remains unattainable, as in Kant's regulative idea.

30. Opravdanie dobra, p. 305.

31. Continuity can be viewed as a unity through time and/or through space. Continuity through time was a subject dear to Solov'ev. He emphasised the value of a bond with ancestors, of tradition. Continuity through space was a subject of concern that he translated into the religious field, by ardently advocating the unification of the churches.

32. Opravdanie dobra, p. 498. transl. p. 422.

33. This formula is strikingly similar to that of Auguste Comte [see subsection 2c].

34. 'Kitaj i Evropa', SS. 6, pp. 93-150: p. 148. In this text, he also used the term kitaizacita to refer, on the basis of the cliche of Chinese conservatism, to the tendency towards stagnation in Russian society. Interestingly, Sergej Solov'ev used the term 'Buddhism' in a similar sense to characterise a fear of progress (Sergej Solov'ev, Socinenija v 18 knigakh (Moskva: Mysl', 1988-1996), vol. 16, pp. 357-66).

35. Influenced by positivism, the term progress, despite its vagueness, had a fantastic impact in the Russian press of the 1870s.

36. See 'Kitaj i Evropa' for a discussion or the term progress.

37. 'Kitaj i Evropa', p. 147. See also Opravdanie dobra, p. 422.

38. In principle Solov'ev saw no difference of degree between these different types of progress. The technical improvement of weapons is considered as much a form of progress as social progress (see 'Rukovodjascie mysli "Istoriceskogo Obozrenija'", p. 372).

39. Opravdanie dobra. p. 478. transl. p. 395.

40. The chapter of Opravdanie dobra 'The meaning of war' was later reedited separately (ex.: Smysl vojny (Odessa: Pecatnoe Delo, 1915), which suggests that it was widely read.

41. Opravdanie dobra, p. 478. With this claim he undoubtedly aimed at pacifists like Lev Tolstoj.

42. Ibid., p. 475. About his prediction of the end of wars, read also 'Pervyj sag k polozitel'noj estetike', p. 94. The argumentation is somewhat twisted: the current growth of militarism and military equipment made the fear for a war greater, thus diminished the danger of a real war. He predicted that if war were to occur, it would be the last one. The numerous wars from 1914 up to the present time sourly contradict this statement.

43. Opravdanie dobra, p. 336.

44. Ibid., pp. 337-338.

45. His interpretation which lies at the basis of his 'Byzantinism' was far from reality, and left aside important phenomena taking place in the period just preceding Byzantium's fall, such as forms of humanism and the Renaissance, as G.I. Scetinina has pointed out, in 'Vladimir Solov'ev: istoriceskie vzgljady', in: coll., Istorija i istoriki (Moskva: Nauka, 1995), pp. 229-255: p. 242.

46. Nikolaj Strakhov criticised the dry, formal, artificial (forced conception of continuity based on no proof) character of Solov'ev's views of history (pointed out by Muller 1947, p. 117).

47. In this respect, there was no room for chance in his teleological scheme. Neither did he pay attention to unintended effects, which he arguably did not consider problematic, since in his eyes the initial intention of the agent mattered less than the end result.

48. 'Rukovodjascie mysli "Istoriceskogo Obozrenija'" was devoted in principle to reviewing the journal, for which apparently, Kareev (1850-1931) himself asked the philosopher (Pis 'ma I, p. 70). However, Solov'ev focused on two of the historian's articles on theory of history and about the relationships of historical science with philosophy. The review thus came down to a discussion of Kareev's epistemological position.

49. 'Rukovodjascie mysli "Istoriceskogo Obozrenija"', p. 367. Solov'ev did not indicate to whom he ascribed the task of actual reflection on these concrete objects.

50. Ibid.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 1:19 am

Part 4 of 4

51. Ibid., p. 370. The philosopher mentioned only one criterion of truth in this text, namely 'the law of uninterrupted development' as 'the main truth of any science' (Ibid., p. 371).

52. One of these exceptions is his argument on the formation of the clan, made on the basis of data provided by the sociologist Lewis Henry Morgan on the Indians of North America called Seneka (Opravdanie dobra, p. 290).

53. Sternkopf 1973, p. 354.

54. Opravdanie dobra, p. 292. He completed this genetic explanation by pointing to the religious dimension of patriotism. In this argument, the link between the character of people and its founder was not only historical, but also had a religious dimension (Sternkopf 1973, p. 355). From then on, Solov'ev could easily ground patriotism in religion. This step I identify as a move from a philosophical to a theological register of history.

55. Opravdanie dobra, p. 485. transl. p. 410.

56. Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, p. 189.

57. Ibid., p. 186 ff. He explicitly acknowledged Hegel's merit in having enlightened the relationship part-whole with this analogy to the living organism, which permitted to understand of how the universal process penetrated particular phenomena ('Gegel", SS. 10. p. 318). For an analysis of this point see subsection 2b). On the question whether Solov'ev really took this directly from Hegel, as he wrote, or from Sergej Solov'ev, as I suppose, see paragraphs 2a and 2b.

58. Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, pp. 190-196. synopsis p. 196 reproduced in my introduction, p. 12.

59. Opravdanie dobra, p. 474. transl. p. 397 [italics Solov'ev's].

60. Ibid., pp. 474-475. Cf: This process was taking place in his time: "In this new period, humanity is undoubtedly going [ ... ] towards a greater and greater rapprochement and mutual interpenetration of big groups (clans, peoples, etc.)' ('Iz filosofii istorii', p. 341).

61. 'The whole of the African coast has been divided between European powers' (Opravdanie dobra, p. 474, transl. p. 397).

62. His definition of Westernism was characteristic: 'orientation of social thought and literature which acknowledges the spiritual solidarity of Russia and Western Europe as two joined parts of one cultural-historical whole, which has to include humanity as a whole within itself (entry 'Zapadnik, zapadnicestvo' written for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia (SS. 11, pp. 582-584), p. 582). There, Solov'ev offered his very personal interpretation of the movement of Russian Westernism. Significantly, he stripped away the exclusive focus on Europe that was so characteristic for the tenants of Westernism, and heavily emphasised the universal significance of the questions raised by these thinkers. As to the notions of universality and universalism, Solov'ev used, but only sporadically, the term universal 'nost (Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, PSS. 3, pp. 7-360: p. 310), and universalizm (Opravdanie dobra, pp. 308, 326). He by far preferred the term vsemirnyj. His concept of all-unity is closely associated, and in some cases equivalent with universality ('universality, or all-unity' (Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, p. 680).

63. This point has been rightly emphasised by Ignatow 1997, p. 3.

64. About Solov'ev's polemics with Danilevskij, see: 'Rossija i Evropa', Nacional' nyj vopros book I (S. 1989 I. pp. 333-396), and the far more balanced entry 'Danilevskij' (SS. 10, pp. 498-505).

65. Solov'ev took up the scheme of the conflict East-West from the Slavophiles [see above chapter II. 'Theology of History in Solov'ev'] and found confirmation of its adequacy in his father's work [see subsection 2b of this chapter].

66. See' Kitaj i Evropa', op. cit. For a detailed account of Solov'ev's views on China, see Setnickij 1926. Setnickij's article is one of the very few writings of the early Soviet period on Solov'ev. In his account of Solov'ev's and Fedorov's views on China as the initiators of the Russian view on China, he distinguished two main phases of Solov'ev's relationship to China: a first, conciliatory phase (up to the 1890s), in which the philosopher advocated Europe to convert China, and a second, defensive phase of a threat from China, and the Far East in general, best expressed in his poem 'Panmongolizm' (SS. 12. pp. 95-96).

67. 'Humanity, though divided in a plurality of alienated and hostile clans and peoples, has never lost the consciousness of its inner unity and of its strife to realize its unity in a practicable way' ('Vsemirnaja monarkhija', SS. 12, pp. 563-564: p. 563). See also Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, p.185.

68. Opravdanie dobra, pp. 476-478, transl. pp. 399-401. These events are narrated in a text penetrated with eschatological motives, namely 'Kratkaja povest' ob Antikhriste'. On world monarchy, see subsection eiii).

69. The only attempt to make a geographical repartition of nations can be found in a draft of La Sophia, (p. 72).

70. Solov'ev, though, never referred to this crucial contribution by Herder to philosophy of history.

71. Solov'ev used the terms narod and nacija indifferently (see Opravdanie dobra, pp. 375, 367). Correspondingly, nacional 'nyj and narodnyj are used as equivalents. Narodnost' means nationality (Ibid., p. 357), national character (Ibid., p. 369), or nation (Ibid., pp. 367, 473).

72. Opravdanie dobra, pp. 357-379.

73. The attempts by the Spaniards to protect and propagate the Christian faith lay close to his own motivations expressed in his theology of history.

74. He did however admit to the existence of national hostility as a 'zoological fact.' (Opravdanie dobra, p. 377, transl. p. 296).

75. Sternkopf defends the idea of a subordination (Sternkopf 1973, p. 345ff.).

76. Opravdanie dobra, p. 503-504.

77. L'idee russe, p. 89.

78. The problem arising from this terminological vagueness between state in the broad and the narrow sense, as well as between state and nation, is that Solov'ev did not take into account some limited cases, for example the Jews in Solov'ev's time. He called them a nation, although they did not have a state in the narrow sense, and were not called a state in the broad sense. Solov'ev failed to acknowledge that there was a problem if one amalgamates the terms nation and state.

79. Definitions from The New Oxford Dictionary of English (2001), p. 1816.

80. A possible explanation for the quasi-absent treatment of the functioning of the state in his philosophical register of history is that he actually had little interest in the functioning of political regimes. He admitted that he was not familiar with discussions about constitution, for instance (Pis 'ma 2, p. 84).

81. Opravdanie dobra, p. 456.

82. 'Sur la question sociale', in: E. 1978. pp. 299-304: p. 302.

83. On this notion in Solov'ev's work. see chap. IV. subsection eiii.

84. Opravdanie dobra, p. 299.

85. Cf.: 'The interests of the whole of humanity do not exist for the state and for the secular government, the duties of which are limited to the fraction of human kind to which it is ascribed' (L'idee russe, pp. 98-99).

86. Although he did not explicitly favour absolute, constitutional or parliamentary monarchy, he does not seem to have opposed popular representation (see for instance his entry on Joseph-Marie de Maistre, 'Mestr', SS. 10, pp. 429-435, in which his disapprobation of the French thinker's political position appears between the lines).

87. Yet a cultural realisation had already taken place in the European civilisation ('Vsemirnaja monarkhija', p. 564).

88. 'Iz filosofii istorii'. p. 346.

89. Opravdanie dobra p. 287.

90. As 'bearers of a higher consciousness, of a better personal and social morality', they were 'benefactors of humanity' or 'heroes' of history (Opravdanie dobra, p. 299, transl. p. 212). These people struggled for a broader social life than the clan, broke up with it, and founded states and cities. Solov'ev considered the personal exploit, which breaks the existing social limits in order to form new and higher forms of social and political life, a fundamental fact (Ibid.). One cannot help wondering whether Solov'ev saw himself a hero of his time, trying to promote his views on a new, theocratic, rule.

91. Solov'ev gave examples or these geniuses mentioned in the previous paragraph. Concerning Adam Smith and Darwin, he ironically advanced that fortunately these people were not aware of the influence of their nationality on their scientific works, or else they would have spent much energy protecting themselves against this influence (' Ljubov' k narodu i russkij narodnyj ideal', Nacional 'nyj vopros I, S. 1989 1, pp. 293-311: p. 298).

92. Examples of political heroes of Western European history can be found in Solov'ev's texts, but are never the object of an analysis. See for instance Joan of Arc, whose 'national' and supra-national' significance' was only briefly discussed in a footnote ('Ljubov' k narodu i russkij narodnyj ideal', pp. 299, 300).

93. Opravdanie dobra, p. 295, transl. p. 213. From the examples Solov'ev gave, it appears that the individual actor of history is a man rather than a woman. In our eyes, the common woman is rather badly treated in Solov'ev, since he ascribes to her only a 'passive' and 'conservative' principle, which he highly valued as 'embodiment of moral heroism' (Ibid., p, 296, transl. p. 214).

94. Worth mentioning are his considerations on the history of personal consciousness. However, they also belong in part to the register of theology of history, since he viewed personal consciousness through the prism of the history of religion, namely through Buddhism, Hinduism, Platonism, Christianity (Opravdanie dobra, pp. 308-328).

95. Sternkopf has pointed to this aspect (Sternkopf 1973, pp. 213-215).

96. Solov'ev went as far as to claim that participation in progress involves one's position regarding all domains, including art, and, logically, the rejection of art for art's sake, which he saw as a form of regression and separatism from the general progress ('Pervyj sag k polozitel'noj estetike', p. 95).

97. A study on the influence of the evolutionistic theories of Darwin, Spencer and Haeckel on Solov'ev would shed light on the role of theories of evolution in Solov'ev's work. This issue, however, goes beyond the scope of my research.

98. 'He not only understood the essence of the Hegelian triad, but also used it himself constantly in his considerations' (Losev 200, p. 172): see also Ignatow 1997, p. 11.

99. The Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte were first known in Russia by the Russian Hegelians of the 1840s. Russian thinkers had been eager to read Hegel and a whole generation of scholars passionately debated his philosophy. For a general introduction of the reception of Hegelianism in Russia, see Guy Planty-Bonjour, Hegel et la pensee philosophique en Russie 1830-1917 (La Haye: Martinus Nijhoff. 1974), chap. 1: 'Diffusion de I'hegelianisme', pp. 8-37. Solov'ev's father himself had the opportunity to read them, as he related in his memoirs: S[ergej] Solov'ev, Moi zapiski dlja detej moikh. a esli mozno, i dlja drugikh (1st publ. 1907: Petrograd, n.p., 1914), p. 60. It was all the more surprising that Vladimir Solov'ev most probably did not know of Hegel's central work on philosophy of history in his early years, as his goal to apply Hegel in the field of history (in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija) shows. The only explanation, though unsatisfactory, could be the fact that Hegel was completely out of fashion in Solov'ev's generation. Obviously, Solov'ev filled this lacuna in the 1890s: he referred to this work in his article on Hegel for the encyclopaedia Brokgauz-Efron.

100. La Sophia (op. cit.), Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija (op. cil.), 'Gegel" (SS. 10, pp. 300-321), Opravdanie dobra (op. cit.).

101. Interestingly, Solov'ev, who was responsible for the philosophy section of the encyclopaedia, had first suggested to Cicerin and Lopatin that they write the entry on Hegel, which both refused, 'thus I will have to take it myself' (Pis 'ma 2, p. 322). The text of the entry was reprinted as the post face of a general work about Hegel written by an English scholar and translated into Russian: 'Filosofija Gegelja', in: E. Kerd, Gegel, S.N. Trubeckoj (transl.) (Moskva: tip.-lit. T-va Kusnereva i Ko., 1898).

102. G.L. Kline, 'Hegel and Solovyov', in: J.J. O'Malley, K.W. Algozin and F. G. Weiss (eds.), Hegel and The History of Philosophy (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974), pp. 159-170; J.L. Navickas, 'Hegel and the Doctrine or Historicity of Vladimir Solovyov', in: The Quest for the Absolute, Boston College Studies in Philosophy, vol. 1, F.J. Adelmann (ed.) (Chestnut Hill: Boston College, 1966 & The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff: 1966), pp. 135- 54; A.N. Golubev, 'Gegel' i VI. Solov'ev: granicy idealisticeskoj dialektiki' in: Doklady X Mezdunarodnogo gegel evskogo kongressa Moskva 26-31 avgusta 1974g., book 2 (Moskva: n.p., 1974), pp. 73-87. On the history of Hegelianism in Russia, see especially Planty-Bonjour 1974, pp. 232-240.

103. Navickas 1966, p. 154. It is this 'Christian historicism' that I have identified and elaborated as 'theology of history', on the one hand, and as 'sophiology of history', on the other. I extend Navickas' investigation by including some works, which he docs not use in his article, such as Solov'ev's article on Hegel for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia.

104. 'In his early works, Solov'ev was [ ... ] systematically Hegelian in metaphilosophy and systematically neo-Hegelian in philosophy, even though he assigned Hegel a rather reduced role in the history of speculative thought. Later he came to confess to Hegel more honestly and more openly' (Kline 1974, p. 169).

105. Ch. Helferich. G.W.F. Hegel, Sammlung Metzler, vol. 182 (Stuttgart: J.B. Metzlersche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1979), pp. 72-3.

106. ‘Gegel", p.318 [italics Solov'ev's].

107. <Plany i cernoviki>, PSS. 2, p. 177.

108. Hegel, Science of Logic, I. Miller (transl.) (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1989).

109. See Krizis zapadnoj filosofii [1874], Teoreticeskaja filosofija [1898-]. For an analysis of Hegelian dialectics in Solov'ev from the perspective of logic, see Planty-Bonjour 1974, pp. 232-240. Surprisingly. Solov'ev's article for the encyclopaedia, the major text on Hegel written by him, although mentioned, is not discussed in Planty-Bonjour's study; nor is Solov'ev's early work Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija. On the understanding of dialectics as an expression of all-encompassing love, see chapter IV 'Solov'ev's Sophiology of History'.

110. 'Gegel", pp. 310-311.

111. La Sophia, p. 108.

112. The fact that this overview is extremely schematic does not plead for Solov'ev's misuse of Hegel's method, since schematism in dialectics was a typical feature of Hegel himself. Losev has also noted this aspect in Solov'ev (Losev 2000, p. 172).

113. Solov'ev put the definition of dialectics in the mouth of Sophia, hereby implying that his own application of it to history, achieved later (Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, 1877) was suggested to him by Divine wisdom.

114. As a matter or fact, in the Lectures on Philosophy of History, Hegel characterised development [Entwieklung] in two steps. First of all, he used the analogy with living organisms in order to show the aspect of self-making: the entity is a organic whole which undergoes dynamic changes by which all parts are affected and then evolve towards a more advanced form, in virtue of an inner unchangeable principle. Secondly, he showed the fundamental difference between the organic unmediated, unhindered development from one stage to the other, and the development of the Spirit which, because of the mediation of consciousness, encounters opposition (Hegel, Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, 'Einleitung', p. 75. English translation: G.W.F. Hegel, Reason in History: A General Introduction to the Philosophy of History (Indianapolis & New York: The Library of Liberal Arts. 1953), p. 69).

115. Solov'ev defined development as 'a series [rjad] of immanent changes of an organic being, which goes from a certain start and is oriented towards a certain determined goal: such is the development of every organism; infinite development is simply nonsense, contradictio in adjecto') (Filosofski nacala cel'nogo znanija, p. 187). This definition remained unchanged twenty years later in the entry 'Mirovoj process' in the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia (SS 10, pp. 247-250).

116. Filosofski nacala cel'nogo znanija p. 188.

117. On the basis of Filosofski nacala cel'nogo znanija, Kline has argued in favour of Solov'ev's use of Hegelian dialectics, though with two qualifications. According to him, in Solov'ev's work, though 'in an subordinate sense, I suppose, the development of one-sided principles -- principles which are "abstract" in Hegel's sense of the term, i.e., "one-sided, inadequately related, relatively unmediated" -- into integral principles -- principles which are "concrete" in Hegel's sense, i.e., "many-sided, adequately related, complexly mediated" -- may be considered a historical, as well as a structural and dialectical, development' (Kline 1974, pp. 165- 6). Concreteness is expressed by Solov'ev as 'cel'nost" [wholeness, literally, often translated as 'integrality']. Kline's reservation that this should apply 'in a subordinate sense' may be related to the fact that only principles, and not, for instance, phenomena are understood in that way.

118. Kline 1974, p. 165. 'Perhaps, Solov'ev's clearest difference from Hegel -- as well as from Plato, Aristotle, and Spinoza -- lies in his refusal to subordinate either doing [social- moral and political institutions. MC] or making [art and mysticism, or creativity, MC] to knowing' (Ibid.). Through this extension of dialectics, Solov'ev obtained an abolition of the domination of knowledge over the other fields.

119. Solov'ev identified a highest form of human activity, which is not knowledge, nor the practical activity of society, but creativity; and within creativity, mysticism holds the highest rank (Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, p. 195).

120. Hegel focused exclusively on the 'immanent side of the absolute idea which moves the world forward', and 'mixed up the world-soul with the absolute', which 'always remains transcendent' ('Gegel", p. 319). In opposition. Solov'ev repeatedly stressed God's transcendence. His change of position with respect to the question whether to use dialectics to define the absolute, the divine, is therefore obvious.

121. 'Gegel", p. 319.

122. Solov'ev's vehemence can be understood as a reaction to his own investigations on the nature of the absolute and its relation to process, formulated in his early works, such as in the Sixth Lecture on Divine Humanity. See Solov'ev's considerations on the essence of God and of Sophia, and his discussion with Schelling [chapter IV 'Solov'ev's Sophiology of History'].

123. Teoreticeskajaja filosofija, S. 1988 1. pp. 757-831: p. 829 [italics Solov'ev's].

124. But this tragic colour seems to disappear in Hegel's idea of the achievement of the objective Spirit in the state. In this tension between the tragic and a goal described in dogmatic terms, probably lies one of the most original aspects of Hegel's philosophy of history.

125. Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, p. 77, transl. p. 70.

126. Ibid., p. 32, transl. p. 24.

127. Hegel's Philosophy of Right. T.M. Knox (transl.) (1st publ. 1952; Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1967), §§ 142-157, pp. 104-110. Cf. Solov'ev: 'The genuine objective morality consists for man in serving consciously and freely this general goal, identifying it with his own personal will, and this identification, which is at the same time man's liberation, will necessarily be achieved when he becomes aware of the truth of this idea. "Get to know the truth, and truth will make you free'" ('Iz filosofii istorii', p. 350).

128. For both, Christianity is the most significant turning point in history (on Hegel see also Helferich 1979, p. 87). For both, it was under the influence of Christianity that the consciousness of human freedom that man as free had appeared. The difference is that Hegel situated it as the turning point between the second phase (Greco-Roman) and the third phase (Christian-German), whereas for Solov'ev it happened within the third phase (Jews). Concerning the last crucial turning point according to Hegel, namely the Reformation, which extended freedom to the mundane world and to all, it is reduced in Solov'ev to a form of protest against Church, simply a form of negative Christianity (La Sophia, p. 150). As far as the predecessors of the Christians are concerned, namely the Jews, Hegel showed that they had played a crucial role, which was equated to the 'absolute turning point' (see Jean Hyppolite, Introduction a la philosophie de l'histoire de Hegel (Paris: Seuil, 1983), p. 54 ff). By contrast, the Jews are strikingly absent from the philosophical register of history that Solov'ev gave in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija. From his theology of history, we know that Solov'ev ascribed them a central role in world history [see also case study III 'The Jewish Question]. A possible explanation for this contrast is that Solov'ev developed a sustained interest in the Jewish people only some years later, in the mid-1880s.

129. This difference has been pointed out by S.B. Rocinskij, in 'Gegelevskie elementy v metafiziceskoj sisteme Solov'eva, in: Ibid., Vladimir Solov'ev i zapadnaja mysl': kiritika, primirenie, sintez (Moskva: Dzangar, 1999), pp. 44-55: p. 46.

130. As a matter of fact, of the 23 pages of the account of world history in Filosofskie nacala cel 'nogo znanija, nearly one third. i.e. 7 pages, are devoted to the future, sketched as the last phase or synthesis and reconciliation of all hostile elements.

131. ‘Gegel", pp. 319-320.

132. Ironically, by not including Russia in the dialectical process that governs history, Solov'ev agreed with Hegel, for whom Russia and the Slavic countries were in principle not bound to play a historical role. This stands in sharp contrast with Solov'ev's many efforts spent to promote the idea of Russia's future universal mission.

133. For instance, 'nation' in the broad sense appears in the expression 'die germanische Nation' (Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, p. 422), meaning all the Germanic peoples at the end of the Roman empire, and in the narrow sense in 'die Englische Nation', when Hegel commented on the modern phenomenon of the English constitution (Ibid., p. 536).

134. See Philosophy of Right, pp. 217-8.

135. Opravdanie dobra, p. 363.

136. In another passage he explained that the unity of nations is produced by three main factors: a physical bond, language, and history (Opravdanie dobra, pp. 501-504). These factors are problematic. It indeed remains unclear what Solov'ev meant by 'physical bond', either ethnicity or a geographical situation: equally problematic is the question of the language: did Solov'ev promulgate one language in one nation, as he here seemed to suggest? From other sources, we know that this was not the case [see case study IV 'The Polish question']. Finally, the issue of national history rests upon an unproblematised definition or nation.

137. A nationality or national character is 'not something self-existent and self-contained, living in itself and for itself, for this great nation proves to be simply a special form of universal content, living in that content, filled with it and embodying it not for itself only but for all' (Opravdanie dobra p. 288). The distinction in nations has to remain till the end of history: 'National differences must remain till the end of time: nations must subsist as really distinct members of the universal organism' (L idee russe, p. 99).

138. Nevertheless, the distinction in nations has to remain till the end of history: 'National differences must remain till the end of time: nations must subsist as really distinct members of the universal organism' (L 'idee russe, p. 99).

139. Cf. Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, p. 114.

140. Opravdanie dobra, p. 368. However, Solov'ev later rejected the cyclic view of the development and decay of nations, when he said: 'Nations will not perish. The soul of Spain can resurrect' ('Nemezida', p. 70). This quotation shows that his conception of nations was contaminated by theological motives.

141. 'Nravstvennost' i politika: istoriceskie objazannosti Rossii', Nacional'nyj vopros V.S. 1989 1, pp. 264-279; p. 264.

142. Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, p. 57, transl. p. 53. As such the state becomes the mediation [Vermittlung] between the divine and the human at the level of the objective Spirit.

143. 'Gegel", p. 315.

144. Philosophy of Right, addition 152 to § 258, p. 279. Hegel's usage of the term 'state' was ambiguous, as was Solov'ev's. He understood state in the broad sense of an entity incorporating spiritual phenomena, as well as in a restricted sense, as 'political state.' For a discussion of these definitions, see Joseph McCarney, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Hegel on History (London & New York: Routledge, 2000), pp. 157-158.

145. Cf. Enzyklopadie, part III (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970), § 552.

146. Solov'ev was explicit when it came to criticising Hegel's concept of national mission: see 'Cto trebuetsja ot russkoj partii?', Nacional'nyj vopros I. S. 1989 1. pp. 327-333: p. 330).

147. Opravdanie dobra, p. 452-453. transl. p. 406.

148. 'Iz filosofii istorii', p. 349.

149. Opravdanie dobra, p. 265, transl. p. 178.

150. Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, p. 96, transl. p. 87. In reaction to Kant's conception of Moralitat in exclusively individual terms, Hegel distinguished it from ethical life [Sittlichkeit], which refers to the objective Spirit in its normative aspect, as embodiment in the institutions and in social life. Solov'ev did not make this distinction, and considered that the same nravstvenmost' was operating in both individual and social life (see for instance Opravdanie dobra, p. 415)

151. Ludwig Heyde, De verwerkelijking van de vrijheid: een inleiding in Hegels rechtsfilosofie (Leuven: Universitaire Pers Leuven, 1987) pp. 209-210.

152.Opravdanie dobra, p. 264, transl. p. 177.

153. See for instance Solov'ev's interventions after the condemnation of the murderers of tsar Alexander II [case study 1].

154. Compare with Hegel, Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschicte, pp. 46-49, transl. pp. 39-43.

155. 'Neskol'ko slov v zascitu Petra Velikogo', Nacional'nyj vopros 2. S. 1989 1, pp. 414-433. Compare with Hegel: 'It is different with large relations in history. This is precisely where great collisions arise between the existing acknowledged duties, laws and rights, and those possibilities which are opposed to this fixed system, harm it and destroy its foundation and reality, and which at the same time have a content which can be good, globally speaking advantageous, essential and necessary. These possibilities then become historical: they involve a general principle of a different order from that which provides the basis in the existence of a people or a state. This principle is a moment in the development of the productive idea, a moment of truth striving and urging towards itself. Historical men, world-historical individuals are those in whose aims such a general principle lies' (Vorlesungen uber die Philosophie der Geschichte, pp. 44-45, transl. p. 39).

156. This is at least what Solov'ev stated with respect to Peter the Great ('Vizantizm i Rossija', p. 578).

157. For a discussion of the problem of internal and external purposiveness with respect to the cunning or Reason in Hegel, see McCarney 2000, p. 129.

158. Istorija Rossii s drevnejsikh vremen (1st publ. 1851-1879). Edition used: Socinenija v vosemnadcati knigakh (Moskva: Mysl', 1988-1996).

159. Sergej Solov'ev developed his philosophy of history in his historical works as well as in essays such as 'Istoriceskie pis'ma' (1958), 'Progress i religija' [1868], 'Nabljudenija nad istoriceskoj zizn'ju narodov' (1868-1876), in: S. Solov'ev 1988-1996 16, pp. 353-404, 673- 92, and 17, pp. 215-238. Solov'ev did confess his father's influence in the field of Christian faith and ethics, as we have seen in chap. II, n. 55]. Even so significantly, he rendered a significant homage to Sergej Solov'ev by dedicating to him his comprehensive work of ethics Opravdanie dobra.

160. Luk'janov 1990 1, p. 147. History professor Vladimir Ger'e was indulgent with Solov'ev and at his final exams did not demand a special knowledge of history, since 'I knew that even as a gymnasium student he had read all the volumes of his father's history that had been published up till then, and he had a phenomenal memory. (Ibid.: quoted in S. Solovov 2000 1. p. 59).

161. Sternkopf emphasised the distance between father and son (Sternkopf 1973. p. 4).

162. Ol’ga Kazak, Teoretiko-metodologiceskie osnovanija koncepcii russkoj istorii S.M. Solov’eva (PhD thesis Moskva: Moskovskij gosudarstvennyj universitet, 1987). Ana Siljak, ‘Christianity, Science, and Progress in Sergei M. Solov’ev’s History of Russia’, in: Thomas Sanders (ed.), Historiography of Imperial Russia. The Profession and Writing of History in a Multinational State (Armonk & London: M.E. Sharpe, 1999), pp. 215-238. Both include a comprehensive bibliography on the Russian and Soviet reception of Sergej Solov’ev’s philosophical views on history. Sergej Solov’ev as a philosopher of history, and especially his concept of progress, was the object of my article, ‘Russische en westerse geschiedfilosofie: voorwaarden voor een vergelijking’, Wijsgerig Perspectief 1999-2000, 4, pp. 110-115.

163. Quoted in Kazak 1987, p. 55. Cf. also: 'We do not have the right to invent special laws of development of the peoples, except the well-known laws of development of an individual human being and of all that is organic' ('Nahljudenia nad istoriceskoj zizn'ju narodov', p. 107). For an excellent analysis of the understanding of the history of the Russian nation within a universal process, and the complexity of such an approach that sought to explain 'how laws of historical development that were in principle universal and uniform could operate to produce such different results in different societies' and 'why Russia was and why it was not European', see Mark Bassin, 'Turner, Solov'ev, and the "Frontier Hypothesis": The Nationalist Significance of Open Spaces', Journal of Modern History 65 (1993), 3, pp. 473-511, esp. pp. 481-484, 490-503, 508-509, quotation p. 490.

164. See in particular 'Nahljudenija nad istoriceskoj zizn'ju narodov'.

165. See subsection 2a) about Solov'ev combining the organic and the dialectic concept of development.

166. 'Po povodu poslednikh sobytij', SS. 10, pp. 222-228: p. 223. This shows that Sergej Solov'ev in this statement used a variant of the organicistic metaphor, namely the analogy of humanity with a human being.

167. The tentative translation of the term druzina by 'militia' was proposed in Siljak 1999, p. 224.

168. Like his son, Solov'ev's father did not make a sharp distinction between nation and people, and commonly used the Russian term narod to refer to people and/or nation. Both valued nationality [narodnost'] positively. It would he plausible to ascribe this to an influence of Sergej Solov'ev. However, there is documentary evidence that Solov'ev specifically discussed Samarin's view on narodnost' [see case study IV 'The Polish Question']. I therefore agree with Sternkopf that Solov'ev picked up the positive valuation of nationality from certain Slavophiles (Sternkopf 1973, pp. 399-403).

169. Opravdanie dobra, p. 366.

170. Sternkopf 1973. p. 265. Solov'ev's references differed from his father's, however. Whereas the model of China inspired the historian, the philosopher rather referred to the world monarchies or universal monarchies, which were alluded to in the Book of Daniel in the Old Testament. This book tells about a king who dreams about four monarchies, symbolised by a statue made up of four different materials. Solov'ev followed the tradition of interpreting these (see Pomian 1984, p. 106) by identifying them as the Assyrio- Babylonian, the Median-Persian, the Macedonian-Hellenic, and the Roman Empire. See also Solov'ev's entry 'Vsemirnaja monarkhija', op. cit.

171. Sternkopf 1973, pp. 261-2.

172. Ibid., p. 285.

173. 'The [s]tate, as the authentic historical embodiment of human solidarity, is the practical condition of humanity's universal concern, that is, the realisation of Good in the world' ('Znacenie gosudarstva', S. 1989, 2. pp. 549-561: p. 555. English translation in Wozniuk 2000. 'The Significance of the State', pp. 45-64: p. 59). In this article, devoted to the history of the conception of state, Solov'ev criticised all models of the state in Greek, Roman, Byzantine, and Western society.

174. Opravdanie dobra, p. 263.

175. In the state, morality has evolved and manifests itself as patriotism and civic virtue, which are one stage higher than morality in family and clan life. It has also evolved in the sense of the appearance of a collective morality, which affects all people [Opravdanie dobra pp. 286-288. transl. p. 204-207].

176. See 'Vzgljad na istoriju ustanovlenija gosudarstvennogo porjadka v Rossii do Petra Velikogo' (S. Solov'ev 1988-1996 16, pp. 5-420).

177. Siljak 1999, p. 227.

178. See Opravdanie dobra, and articles, primarily 'Znacenic gosudarstva', op. cit.

179. Opravdanie dobra, p. 461. transl. p. 383.

180. Ibid.

181. Ibid., pp. 460-461.

182. Ibid., p. 338.

183. It would be interesting to know which authors, thinkers, people Solov'ev had in mind when he referred to the moral preach: liberal thinkers like his father, Slavophiles committed in the liberation of the serfs? Anyway the state is the main force at stake precisely because it is inspired by views that come from educated society.

184. Sternkopf 1973, p. 298. See for instance Opravdanie dobra, p. 365-366.

185. See for instance Opravdanie dobra, pp. 295-296.

186. Most probably, the historian picked up the category from Hegel via his professor at University, Timofej Granovskij. See Planty-Bonjour 1974, p. 13, 21-32, 250. See also Dmitrij Tschizewskij, Hegel bei den Slaven (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. 1961), 'Hegel in Russland'. pp. 145-396: on Granovskij, see pp. 229-236. On the influence of Hegel on the state school, see A.N. Medusevskij, 'Gegel' i gosudarstvennaja skola russkoj istoriografii', in: coll., Rossija i Germanija: Opyt filosofskogo dialoga (Moskva: Medium, 1993), pp. 146-174.

187. Sergej Solov'ev, 'Publicnye ctenija o Petre Velikom', S. Solov'ev 1988-1996 18, pp. 8-11.

188. Sternkopf 1973, p. 440. Unfortunately, Sternkopf does not further specify this borrowing.

189. Compare Sergej Solov'ev, 'Publicnye etenija o Petre Velikom' (pp. 5-152), with Vladimir Solov'ev, 'Neskol'ko slov v zascitu Petra Velikogo', pp. 414-433.

190. See 'Vizantizm i Rossija', esp. pp. 581-586.

191. Compare Sergej Solov'ev, 'Istorija Rossii s drevnejsikh vremen (Fragment)', in: D.K. Burlaka, A.A. Kara-Murza, K.E. Nemuzilov, L.V. Poljakov, R.V. Svetlov (eds.), Petr Velikij: Pro et Contra (Sankt-Peterburg: Izd. Russkogo Khristianskogo gumanitarnogo instituta, 2001), pp. 165-178, esp. p. 165: Vladimir Solov'ev, "Neskol'ko slo v zascitu Petra Velikogo', p. 414.

192. This specific interest in religious and ethical questions appears from the title of a short essay, Religiozno-nravstvennoe sostojanie russkogo obscestva pred reformoj Petra Velikogo (n,p., 1877), signed 'VI. Solov'ev.' Despite the thematic similarity, we cannot, however, conclude that it was the philosopher who wrote this essay. There arc striking differences which suggest that a homonym author wrote this essay, such as an extensive use of references, the detailed anthropological treatment of ethics in domestic life, as well as a reference to another work of the same author (p. 10) which so far nobody has ascribed to Vladimir Sergeevic Solov'ev ('Ostatki jazyceskikh verovanij", Strannik 1877, 9).

193. Sternkopf 1973, p. 262.

194. As Scetinina points out, Solov'ev was the most significant critic of positivism in Russian idealist philosophy. However, Mikhajlovskij reproached him for not making a distinction between positivism and materialism (Scetinina 1995. p. 232).

195. Krizis zapadnoj filosofii (protiv positivistov) (PSS. I. pp. 38-138: 'Prilozenie: teorija Ogjusta Konta o trekh fazisakh v umstvennom razvitii celovecestva' (Ibid., pp. 139-152): 'Kont (SS. 10. pp. 380-409); 'Ideja celovecestva u Avgusta Konta' (SS. 9. pp. 172-193: p. 172).

196. The role of Comte in shaping Russian positivism was downplayed by Soviet historians of Russian philosophy. The publication of the collection Ogjust Kont: vazljad iz Rossii (K.Kh. Delokarpov and H.M. Sakhmatov (eds.) (Moskva: Izd. RAGS. 2000) successfully changed this situation. For an outline of the history of Comte's reception in Russia, see B.M. Sakhmatov. 'O, Kont i russkaja mysl", in: Ogjust Kont: vazljad iz Rossii pp. 50-67. That Solov'ev is considered a key figure is apparent from the fact that the author not only points to Solov'ev as the main initiator of the second period in the reception of Comte, but also quotes Solov'ev in expressing his own opinion of Comte (Ibid., p. 63).

197. Nobody saw this influence, except Florovsky (mentioned in David 1960, p. 30). However, Solov'ev scholars did not fail to notice the evolution of Solov'ev's views on Comte towards a more positive valuation. For Losev 'in the whole history of philosophy, Solov'ev was the only idealist who found highly valuable ideas in the founder of European positivism himself' (Losev 2000, p.176).

198. David 1960, pp. 29-81.

199. S.B. Rocinskij. 'VI. Solov'ev i O. Kont: Cerez kritiku -- k konvergencii', (1st publ. in Rocinskij 1999). in: Ogjust Kont: vazljad iz Rossii , pp. 67-89. Rocinskij recontextualises Solov'ev's interventions on Comte in the movement of protest against positivism which arose in the late 1860s, under the guidance of scholars with whom Solov'ev was in contact, such as his professor Pavel Jurkevic, but also Viktor Kudrjavcev-Platonov and Nikolaj Strakhov.

200. David 1960, p. 31.

201. The idea of the three stages was expressed in his works from 1822 onwards, and then permanently reworked, for instance in his Cours de philosophie positive (1830-1842), Discours sur l'esprit positif (1844), and Systeme de politique positive (1851-1854). See Comte, Discours sur l'esprit positif (Paris: Vrin 1995). p. 41, n. l.

202. Discours sur l'esprit positif, pp. 30 n:

203. For a philosophical account of Solov'ev's criticism of Comte's law of the three stages, see Tatjana J. Kochetkova, Vladimir Solov'jov 's Theory of Divine Humanity (Kiev: Blago, 2001). pp. 13-17.

204. For instance, Solov'ev criticised Comte's view of fetishism as the first period of the theological stage. According to him, religion originated rather in the image of the parents. On this point he rather agreed with Spencer, according to whom religion derives from the cult of ancestors (Opravdanie dobra, p. 176).

205. For instance, when Comte characterised theology as the stage where 'all our speculations spontaneously manifest a characteristic predilection for the less solvable questions, the subjects which are the most radically inaccessible to any definitive investigation' (Discours sur l'esprit positif, p. 43).

206. See for instance Comte's characterization of metaphysics as ontology (Discours sur l'esprit positif, p. 57).

207. Krizis zapadnoj filosofii, p. 72.

208. Discours sur l'esprit positif, pp. 41. 42 (n. 1).

209. Hereby Solov'ev referred to the religion of humanity professed by Comte in his later years.

210. ‘Kont', pp. 399-400. Hereby Solov'ev referred to religious philosophy not only in his own country, and to which he brought a central contribution, but also to French fideism and Christian rationalism (for instance Philippe Buchez) that flourished under the persisting influence of de Bonald and Lamennais.

211. See for instance Discours sur l'esprit positif, pp. 62-63.

212. 'Kont', p. 400.

213. David 1960, p. 57ff.

214. The account below is drawn from David, who has convincingly shown this point (David 1960, pp. 62-(11).

215. In any case, his scheme does not display much originality. Further information on the possible influence of Hegel on Comte or conversely, and that of Comte on Sergej Solov'ev, who was after all as a historian much influenced by positivism, would help shed light on this matter.

216. This point was obviously overlooked by David.

217. 'Kitaj i Evropa', p. 147.

218. Discours sur l'esprit positif, p. 150.

219. Ibid., p. 149, n.2.

220. There also is a sophiological aspect of Solov'ev's views on humanity that bring him close to Comte's concept of Grand Etre [see chap. IV 'Solov'ev's Sophiology of History'].

221. This is also the opinion of Rocinskij 2000, p. 86. It is piquant to read how, in a letter to the encyclopaedia editor Arsen'ev, Solov'ev defended himself against his 'preference' for Comte's second system, which had a far more religious tenor and in which the concept of humanity was fundamental (see Pis 'ma (12. p. 94).

222. Family and fatherland, 'being consistent preparations to humanity, must not be understood as its real elements or components, for humanity is an indivisible being' ('Ideja celovecestva u Avgusta Konta', p. 185).

223. Ibid., p. 180.

224. Ibid., p. 181. Despite the quotation marks, Solov'ev appears to have modified Comte's text. The German critical edition mentions several omissions, additions and distortions of Comte's text by Solov'ev.

225. In the dictionary Russkaja filosofija, the Russian scholar Piama Gajdenko hastily concluded that Solov'ev had borrowed the concept of humanity from Comte. Rocinskij convincingly argues against this thesis that Solov'ev's views rather came to a 'coincidence, a convergence' (Rocinskij 2000, pp. 85-86, n. 34).
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 7:51 am

Part 1 of 3

IV. Solov'ev's Sophiology of History

As the realisation of the divine principle, its image and likeness, archetypal humanity, or World Soul, is both one and all. World Soul occupies a mediating position between the multiplicity of living entities [ ... ] and the absolute unity of Divinity. [1]


Introduction

Solov'ev's historical intuition was that of a feminine and material entity engaged in the world in a process of spiritualization. This intuition was intimately linked with his mystical visions of Sophia, which were 'so far the most significant event' of his life, as he wrote in 1898 at the age of 45. [2] From the outset of his career, this experience urged him to investigate the topic of Sophia and its doublet, World Soul, in various traditions, the most significant aspects of which he integrated in his own conception, which I label his sophiology. For the sake of ease, I use the expression 'Sophia-World Soul', and in this chapter, I analyse the complex relationship that Solov'ev established between the two components. The fact that his sophiology was far less elaborated as an articulate discourse than his theology of history and his philosophy of history is shown by his many unsuccessful attempts to conceptualise Sophia-World Soul and to find an adequate medium of expression to convey his views. The quasi-absence of a link with specific historical events or characters also suggests that this register is not so much about historicity as about process. However, Solov'ev established a link between Sophia and Russia, which reveals his conviction that Russia was historically bound to incarnate Sophia in a near future.

One of the most fascinating features of Solov'ev's writings is found in his unwavering search for a way to express this sophianic intuition. [3] This chapter seeks to unravel the stage of elaboration and the role of sophiology of history in Solov'ev, and advances the fallowing five theses. Firstly, Sophia-World Soul is intrinsically linked to history, and, conversely, that history, in Solov'ev's eyes, can be best understood in terms of sophianisation. Secondly, a core aspect, which though remains mostly implicit in Solov'ev's work, is that the imminent incarnation of Sophia is the mission that Russia, as the mediator between the divine and the human world, is bound to fulfill under the guidance of the prophet Solov'ev. Thirdly, in his theoretical writings. he only paved the way for sophiology, without realising an articulate '-logy.' Interestingly, Russia's 'most systematic philosopher's' conception of Sophia was dominated foremost by his initial intuition. [4] Fourthly, Sophia-World Soul is the cornerstone of Solov'ev's work as a whole, which he, however, left for the most part concealed. The role of visible cornerstone is performed by the metaphysical principle of all-unity [vseedinstvo], which applies to all things and beings, and by the theological principle of the humanity of God [Bogocelovecestvo], which applies only to human beings. A demonstration of the intimate connection between Sophia-World Soul and the two principles is provided below.

My fifth thesis concerns the relationship between sophiology of history and the two other registers of history. Solov'ev introduced sophiology of history [SH] in order to compensate for the flaws of TH and PH. An exclusively theological view of history leaves the gulf between man and God, between the immanent and the transcendent levels, intact. Philosophy of history is limited in the sense that it focuses on the development of individuals, and humanity, and tends to suppress the level of transcendence. Besides, neither theology of history nor philosophy of history take into account nature and matter in their own value, and as a result do not deal with the world as a whole. Neither is there space in these registers for a type of knowledge that was fundamental for Solov'ev, namely inspiration. In order to overcome the limitations of these two conceptions without giving up their contribution, Solov'ev created a third conception of history, his sophiology of history. Two aspects are central in this register, namely the idea of a fusion between the divine and the world, and a conception of process in which nature also takes part. [5] As a result, this register does not present a sharp historical view, but rather emphasises the process-like character of the rapprochement between the world and God. That Solov'ev saw it as his mission to contribute to this rapprochement shows from his considerations on the affinity of the Russian people with Sophia, and his implicit self-definition as that prophet able to guide Russia on this path.

Solov'ev's personal intuition of Sophia-World Soul, based on his mystical and erotic visions of Sophia, and his perception of World Soul in nature, was so significant to him that he consistently searched for ways to express it. [6] For this purpose, he explored two main genres: speculative essays and poetry. He wrote an essay entirely devoted to Sophia, entitled La Sophia, which remained unpublished until the 1970s. He also wrote passages about Sophia-World Soul in his theological essays Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, La Russie et l'Eglise universelle, and, in a more scattered way, in Smysl ljubvi. [7] Not less importantly, a whole range of Solov'ev's poems deal with Sophia-World Soul. [8] In all these texts, he advanced elements for a sophiology of history. [9]

Below I deal with the following issues: in the first part (1), I give a general definition of SH (a) by clarifying the concepts of (i) Divine Sophia and (ii) Earthly Sophia or World Soul; (b) by characterising the underlying framework, (ci) periodisation, (cii) conception of time, (di) criteria, (dii) method, and (e) the main actors in SH. In the second part (2), I explore the sources from which Solov'ev drew inspiration to construct his sophiology of history, namely (a) the Kabbalah, (b) Gnosticism, (c) Jacob Bohme, and (d) Schelling.

1. The Register of Sophiology of History in Solov'ev

a) General definition


At the age of twenty-one, Solov'ev felt a call to contribute to the process of history in a specific manner. Sophia urged him to build a new synthetic system. or 'universal religion', which not only brought together all fields of knowledge, namely philosophy, religion, and science, but which also integrated the spiritual or inner sphere with the external sphere of social and political life. [10] Significantly, his ambition of system-building lay beyond the purely intellectual field: Solov'ev sought to contribute to the practical or 'real incarnation of Sophia', which he understood as the logical and culminating step after her 'theoretical incarnation' in modern philosophy. [11]

The question of the definition of sophiology in general is problematic. [12] The issue of Sophia-World Soul and her role in Solov'ev's thought is particularly complex, and deserves close attention. It has been the object of renewed scholarly interest over the past ten years. [13] The reasons for this complexity are at least threefold. Firstly, Solov'ev tried to syncretise various traditions, such as the Kabbalah and Gnosticism, and cast them in a nineteenth-century worldview. Secondly, he elaborated on Sophia-World Soul in often conflicting ways, or at least so it appears at first sight. Thirdly, his definition of Sophia- World Soul evolved in the course of his work, which raises the question of whether he rejected or revised previous views or whether he merely shifted focus. It is therefore relevant to first examine the two notions of Sophia specifically, as Divine Wisdom, and as World Soul.

i) Divine Sophia or Divine Wisdom

Throughout his years, Solov'ev consistently defined Sophia first and foremost as the feminine figure of Divine Wisdom, She appeared as such to him in mystical visions, which he narrated in his aptly entitled poem 'Tri svidanija' [Three Encounters]. [14] Her revelations are cast into a discursive form for the first time in a dialogue in La Sophia, where 'Sophia' is the interlocutor of 'the philosopher.' She wants to 'reveal to me the mystery of the three worlds and the future of humanity' and to entrust him with the mission of building a universal religion. [15] Having received this divine impulse, Solov'ev elaborated on Sophia in scholarly discourse. In Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, he defined Sophia as the unity which is produced, as 'God's body, the matter of divinity, permeated with the principle of divine unity.' [16] From the definition as produced unity, it was only one short step to provide Sophia with a teleological dimension: Solov'ev took this step when he characterised her as 'the expressed and actualised idea', 'the ideal or perfect humanity'. or in other terms, the ideal unity between man and God. [17] This conception is elaborated further in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle. Sophia is the substance of Holy Trinity and 'the plenitude or the absolute totality of being, anterior and superior to any partial existence'; [18] as such, Solov'ev argued, she can be identified with the Old Testament Chochmah. [19] By positing Sophia both prior to creation and as that ideal unity that humanity has to achieve, he understood history as the process of actualisation of Sophia, or, which is the same, sophianisation:

In the thought or God, heaven and earth, the higher and the lower world, were created together in one principle, which is the substantial Wisdom, the absolute unity of all. The union of heaven and earth, posed in principle (reshith) in the beginning of the creative work, must he realised in fact by the cosmogonic and historical process leading to the perfect manifestation of this unity in the Kingdom or God (malkhout). [20]


In this quotation, it is clear that his ambition is to posit the transcendent and the immanent levels in terms or fusion. The Russian philosopher also sought to connect his view of Sophia with the living tradition of the veneration of Wisdom [Mudrost' or Premudrost'] in Eastern Christianity, inspired by the Old Testament book or the Proverbs. Solov'ev saw numerous signs or the incarnation of Sophia in the church, from the construction of the basilica Haghia Sophia in Constantinople to the Russian Orthodox icons of Wisdom. It is obvious that his conception of Sophia shares little with the liturgical Orthodox tradition. [21] However, he had the unwavering conviction that his own country was bound to embody Sophia in a concrete and practical way. The link that he made between Sophia and the Russian mission in history forms the core of his self-perception as a prophet [see subsection e] and guided his main interventions in social and political matters [see case studies].

The divine Sophia, as unity between man and God, acts among humans not only in the form of an icon, but, in a far more subversive tone, Solov'ev posed that her most definitive form of incarnation is the spiritual and sexual love between man and woman. Indeed, it is through a mortal woman that a man loves the feminine divine eternal being. [22] In his poetry, Solov'ev narrated his love for Sophia through his encounter with a mortal woman. [23] However, his own mystical experience entitled him to relate to Sophia without the intermediary of an earthly woman: he also directly addressed Sophia as his 'empress', his 'goddess', 'who is not here and not there, in the kingdom of mystical dreams', and saluted her: 'eternal femininity is now coming on earth, in an imperishable body.' [24] Solov'ev saw the mystical union of the true poet with Sophia as a reflection of a process that takes place on the cosmic level, namely the fusion between God and World Soul.

ii) Earthly Sophia or World Soul

Solov'ev had an intuition of Sophia as not only Divine Wisdom, but also as the created, earthly, 'Divided Sophia', or World Soul. [25] The expression' Divided Sophia' suggests to some extent a common nature of Divine Wisdom and World Soul. Initially, in La Sophia, Solov'ev examined the notion of a superior cosmic being called Soul [Ame, Ame universelle], which had wanted exclusive power, and had therefore fallen. [26] Soul also contains in its strife 'the principle of real unity.' The cosmic and historical processes are about the strife of the fallen Sophia or Soul to reunite with God through man and through nature. [27] Solov'ev connected her intimately to history by declaring that Soul 'in its divided and suffering aspect is the matter or the substratum of the process.' [28]

From hereon, he attempted to further conceptualise this double character of World Soul as divided and striving to unity. In Kritika otvleeennykh nacal, [Critique of Abstract Principles, 1877- 1879]. Solov'ev founded the notion of World Soul in a metaphysical framework. He characterised World Soul not only as a free being, thus positing a third free being next to the traditional Christian view of God and man, but he also resolutely defined World Soul as a 'second Absolute' or as 'becoming absolute' through man, in contrast to God's 'being absolute.' [29] As becoming absolute, World Soul contains within herself two main components: the divine clement of all-unity [vseedinstvo], which she possesses only in potency, and the material clement of particularity [to castnoe] or plurality [mnozestvennost']. [30] World Soul is the fundament of all that exists outside God. She is present in nature. but here the divine element is only potential, blind, and unconscious. The divine element receives its 'ideal reality' only in man, and through man, World Soul becomes conscious of herself. [31] In this way, Solov'ev firmly tied the destiny of World Soul to that of men, and equated its ideal form with the theological principle of humanity of God, as well as with the philosophical principle of all-unity. [32] In Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, Solov'ev further specified the nature of World Soul as a 'dual being', both as the present, suffering soul of the world, striving for this ideal of unity with the divine, and as ideal humanity. By this move, he brought World Soul so close to Sophia as to nearly identifying them with one another. [33] World Soul occupied a 'mediating position' between the divine and the human. [34] This definition of World Soul in terms of mediation reinforces Solov'ev's thesis that it is fundamentally through World Soul that the goal of all-unity can be achieved.

At a later stage, Solov'ev abandoned this ambiguous definition of World Soul as half divine, half non-divine, a definition which did not escape the criticism of creating a second absolute next to God that God would need in order to become perfect. [35] As a result, in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, while maintaining the definition of Sophia as divine, he redefined World Soul as the first creature of God. He presented a theologically more acceptable interpretation by radically distinguishing between, on the one hand. Sophia the wisdom of God, as primordial unity between God and creation. and. on the other hand. World Soul -- no longer an intermediary between heaven and earth, but 'the opposite or the antitype of the essential Wisdom of God." In conformity with the earlier definitions, World Soul is 'the materia prima and true substratum of our created world', striving to reunite with the divine in virtue of the divine element present within herself and against the temptations of chaos. [36] So, even though Sophia and World Soul are now separated at their origin. the goal of history still consists in their fusion, and in this sense is close to the theological ideal of the humanity of God. [37]

In his last explicit publication on the issue. namely 'Mirovaja dusa' [World Soul] for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia. Solov 'ev adopted an entirely different tone and spoke of the 'united inner nature of the world' from the perspective of history of philosophy. He described the evolution of the term World Soul in two directions, the one leading from Plato to Schelling, which included a being superior to World Soul, the other leading from Indian philosophies to Schopenhauer and von Hartmann, which in contrast excluded any God. [38] To this scholarly account he added his own position. He criticised the second orientation for not taking into account the 'fact' of a teleological process governing the world. His final judgement was that a consistent understanding of World Soul included a conception of God -- a point in line with his own essays, yet which took him many attempts to conceptualise. A statement made in Smysl ljubvi confirms the thesis that Solov'ev actually saw Sophia and World Soul as two sides of the same coin. The perfect unity of all, symbolised by Sophia, is already a reality for God, while it is for us in the process of realisation. [39] Solov'ev hereby defined an analogical relationship between, on the one hand, Sophia and God (realm of perfection in being), and World Soul and human beings (realm of perfection in becoming), on the other. In other terms, . World Soul is the means by which Sophia bridges the two realms' of matter and spirit. [40] In this sense, Sophia-World Soul allows the conceptualisation of mediation between God and the world, understood as a fruitful tension between being and becoming, eternity and time, transcendence and immanence.

So far Solov'ev had emphasised the incarnation of World Soul in man. In writings such as Opravdanie dobra, 'Krasota v prirode' and 'Obscij smysl iskusstva', he added further elements of the incarnation of World Soul in nature and matter. [41] The view that nature and matter arc involved in the process towards the fusion of World Soul with the divine was present from La Sophia onwards. But in these later writings, although he rarely referred to World Soul, the philosopher made efforts to conceptualise how precisely nature and matter contribute to this process. Firstly, Word Soul defined as nature is the battlefield of the forces of chaos and order. [42] Inorganic, and, far more obviously, organic life incarnates the idea of unity, with each stage an improvement upon the previous stage, and hereby producing beauty. In this argumentation, interestingly, beauty is defined as the result of a process involving the material realm and the spiritual realm, namely as the "transformation of matter through the embodiment in it of another, supra-material principle.' [43] In art, the work of nature is continued. through the incarnation in sensible forms of ideal content. [44] Solov'ev posited this activity as a central contribution to 'integral life' b) defining it as 'free theurgy', next to "free theosophy' and 'free theocracy.' [45] Another way of spiritualising material nature is through agriculture. The philosopher insisted on the moral obligation of treating nature respectfully, and of cultivating it with love for its 'future renewal and regeneration.' [46] More generally, the spiritualization of World Soul in its manifestation as nature of 'material life' was one of the historical tasks of human beings. It thus implied a treatment of matter in economics in respectful rather than instrumental terms. [47] In this sense, the spiritualization of World Soul should be worked at in human activities varying from art to economics and agriculture. In this way he sought to positively value the world in its material it) and to shows that it should be included in the process of spiritualization.

Solov'ev's various attempts to conceptualise Sophia and World Soul should not he seen as failures. but are in themselves deeply significant, and testify to a quest for a place for both notions. However, one can wonder about the meaning of his progressive differentiation between Sophia and World Soul. On the one hand, it can be viewed as a fundamental change, which was dictated notably by the need to present an 'Orthodox' view. On the other hand, Solov'ev's poems reveal that he actually continued to think in terms of a close link, and not an opposition, between earth and heaven, between the material and the spiritual, between a created and an uncreated Sophia. [48] This suggests a change of method, apparent in two moves: an attempt to produce a theologically acceptable discourse on divine Sophia, as we have seen in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, and at the same time, a transfer of the treatment of created Sophia, or World Soul, to the genre of poetry, and, in an underdeveloped way, to the field of aesthetics and economics.

With these two notions of Sophia and World Soul, Solov'ev paved the way for a new theory of creation and history, namely sophiology of history. in which he places an emphasis on the link between the divine and the human in a new way. On the one hand, he does this through positing the feminine figure of Divine Wisdom, which he sought to provide with, as Boris Groys has aptly put it, 'maximal equality' [Gleichberechtigung] with respect to God and, on the other hand, through underscoring the value of the world, which is perceived as a feminine and material entity. [49] In this register, the goal of history consists of reunifying the two Sophias through the incarnation of Divine Sophia by World Soul; all things and beings, that is, not only human beings, but also nature and matter, are involved in the process. Solov'ev identified the becoming incarnation of Divine Sophia by World Soul as the bridging itself of the opposition between transcendence and immanence.

b) Framework

In sophiology of history, a third realm is introduced against the strict distinction between the transcendent and the immanent levels in theology of history and philosophy of history, which is not limited to man, but also includes matter and nature, and which works towards the ultimate unification with God. [50] The characterisation of this third realm varied in Solov'ev's works. First, in La Sophia, it is represented by three cosmic entities, namely Satan, Demiurge and Sophia, which struggle for the power over humanity in history. [51] Later. Solov'ev describes this realm in terms or 'World Soul.' [52] He suppressed the cosmic characters presented in La Sophia, and attempted to cast his views in a theologically and philosophically acceptable discourse, Between the chaotic existence of Earth on the one hand. and the divine light and unity on the other, it was necessary, he said, 'to produce an existence which is half-earthly and half-heavenly, which is able to embrace in its unity the totality of creature and to reattach it to God.' [53] By 'totality of creature' Solov'ev also meant matter, which is included in the cosmic and historical process towards its 'reattachment' with God, in contrast with the framework of theology of history that only has a bearing on human beings. World Soul strives for reunification with God, to 'incarnate in a created form the eternal divine Wisdom.' [54] In this way, Solov'ev attempted to solve the ambiguity of the relationship between World Soul and Sophia.

c) Periodisation and conception of time

i) Periodisation


Characteristic for Solov'ev's efforts to relate Sophia-World Soul to the cosmic and historical process are the periodisations offered in La Sophia, Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, and La Russie et l’Eglise universelle. [55] Prior to the actual occurrence of the process, Solov'ev posed a primordial unity of everything in the divine principle. [56] The ensuing process was provoked by the fall of World Soul. since it wanted freedom and thereby exclusive power. In general terms. the procedure as a whole consists of a history or gradually regaining the primordial unity, through ever-better unifications with the divine principle with World Soul, or 'manifestations of the divine idea (all-unity)' in the world. [57]

Solov'ev distinguished three main phases, in which World Soul appeared in increasingly perfect forms of unity with in itself and with God. The first phase is perhaps sophiology's most original contribution to the theological and philosophical schemes of history. and bears a Gnostic or a Kabbalistic influence [see subsections 2a and 2b]. It properly speaking took place before human history started. This cosmogonic phase witnessed the external manifestation or all-unity in the law of universal gravitation up to the creation of more complex forms of unity in 'vegetative and animal organisms" in which World Soul manifested itself. [58] In the second phase, known as mythological or theogonic, humanity, which now was constituted as an organic body, started to manifest inner unity 'in the form of consciousness and free activity.' [59] Henceforth, World Soul acted through man, who is 'the natural mediator between God and material being', and who, as such, could realise de facto unity and order in the chaotic realm of nature. [60] Through human consciousness, World Soul developed different worldviews or ideas of unity of God with the universe, namely in Buddhist and Hindu civilisation, in Greek philosophy, and in Judaism. [61] Here we encounter the same 'episodes' of world history as in TH, and partly PH, but with a different emphasis. Sophiology of history emphasises the relationship between the divine principle and the World Soul through man, With Judaism, 'a living personal force' was capable of taking possession of the soul for the first time. This process led to the formation of the 'self-consciousness of the human soul as a spiritual principle.' [62] This provided the basis for the third, historical phase. [63]

According to Solov'ev, this last phase started with the life of the God-human individual, the Messiah, Jesus Christ. It was only at this point in time that humanity started to develop into the universal Church, or 'Incarnate Sophia' in its 'universal extension. [64] In La Sophia, the periodisation within each phase is structured by the successive influence of the cosmic principles Satan (from the beginning of Christianity to the Middle Ages), Demiurge (from 1500 to approximately the 19th century), and Soul or Sophia. [65] The latter is of particular interest for our analysis. A first, theoretical, incarnation of Sophia had already taken place in modern philosophy and in the systems of Bohme, Swedenborg, and Schelling, who had laid the basis for universal religion. [66] Under the influence of Sophia- soul, these thinkers, who were able to effectively understand and express her revelations, initiated a philosophy based on the subjective, human soul, which replaced the objective thought of the Ancients and hereby removed the 'theoretical imperfection of Christianity.' [67] Now its practical imperfection, namely only a partial realisation of the Christian message in society by Catholicism, also had to be removed, namely by a Slavic, preferably the Russian people. [68] In a revelation found in automatic writing, Sophia even showed Solov'ev a precise year for what we may understand as her actual incarnation: 'I will be born in April 1878.' [69] Out of this last indication we can deduce that the last stage of history was to start in a very near future. We also can see Solov'ev's direct belief in the concrete advent of 'Incarnate Sophia' and possibly his own role in it. [70]

The philosopher pointed only in passing to 'Incarnate Sophia's' forms of realisation in the three main spheres. Arguably, in the sphere of knowledge, his project of 'universal religion' served this goal. Concerning the social sphere, he hoped for an interaction between individuals and collectivity in terms of love and 'syzygy' [see subsection di]. As to the sphere of creation. since European art had exhausted all forms of art known to us, new forms were bound to come. [71] As he stated in Smysl ljubvi, the goal was perhaps obvious, but the means of attaining it were still unclear. [72] As a matter of fact, he only sketched a first draft of sophiology of history, and the historical content remained undeveloped.

ii) Conception of time

More strongly perhaps than in the two other registers of history. Solov'ev was concerned with drawing a close link between sophiology and time. This is shown by the fact that the three main texts devoted to sophiology contain most of his considerations on time.

In line with his theology of history, Solov'ev envisaged time in a three-fold manner: with respect to nature, to World Soul, and to God. He argued that time in nature is one of the forms of God's heteronomy. Indeed, contrary to the essence of God, which is all-unity. there is in nature an 'undetermined succession of exclusive and indifferent moments. which we call time.' [73] Time in nature is only a mere succession of moments that struggle for existence and are so deprived of any inner bond between them. In this sense. time is not only heteronomous, but also heterogeneous. However, World Soul strives towards unity within itself, and for this purpose has to complete each moment by linking it to the past and to the future. through reminiscing and waiting. Only in this way can World Soul reach total inner subjectivity. [74]

Solov'ev proceeded by linking World Soul more closely with God from the perspective of time. He identified past, present, and future in World Soul with 'its three positions with respect to the Divinity'. which he also called the 'ideal trinity of the three times'. and which echo his periodisation:

[...] the state of her primitive absorption [of the Soul] in the unity of the eternal Father, her eternal subsistence in him as pure potency or simple possibility is henceforth defined as the past of soul; the state of her separation from God by the blind force of chaotic desire constitutes her present; and the return to God, the new reunion with him, becomes the object of her strife and her efforts, her ideal future. [75]


Characteristically. Solov'ev considered the future only in 'ideal' terms of a union with God, and left aside the possible negative outcome of World Soul's freedom, which would incite the world to once again turn away from God. [76] According to Solov'ev, World Soul was bound to reunite with God sooner or later. This view of the future testifies to Solov'ev's deep-seated optimism. [77] As to the implementation of the ideal. Solov'ev had in mind all- nity as defined in the register or philosophy of history, though informed by another force, namely love.

To summarise, a sophiological conception or time is typified by the emphasis on a subjective perception of time, as the elaborations on the necessity far World Soul to experience time show, as well as on the future as the dimension or necessary reunification of World Soul with God.

d) Criteria and method

i) Criteria: cosmic, mystical and erotic love


Arguably, the main criterion that distinguishes the sophiological from the theological and philosophical register or history is love. From a sophiological perspective. love is the motor for the achievement or all-unity, the unifying force between all three above-mentioned levels. that is, God, man. and World Soul, including nature. This criterion has already been pointed out in his theology of history, but in the sophiological register love refers to a broader content. Rather than the traditional Christian view of love as mutual charity between human beings, love consists of the relationship between the masculine and the feminine principle at various levels. He posited love as the cosmic relationship between God and World Soul that want to reunite, as the personal, mystical and erotic relationship between feminine Sophia and the poet-prophet, and as the one-to-one relationship of sexual love as 'real and all-mighty love.' [78]

Solov'ev had already devoted attention to love in Lu Sophia as the 'free and intimate link' between spiritual beings par excellence. [79] Later, he explicitly argued that 'sexual love' in marriage creates the 'true individual elements of true society, of incarnate Sophia.' [80] In Smysl ljubvi, he specifically connected cosmic love to heterosexual love. In the latter, divine substance finds a means to once and for all incarnate itself in individual human life in an altogether profound and external. tangible way. [81] Through the love for a woman, man loves and venerates the heavenly object of love, the feminine divine eternal. Undoubtedly, Solov'ev drew elements of inspiration for this connection between cosmic and human love from his personal experience. Not only does the poet-prophet have contact with Divine Wisdom, but cosmic love and human heterosexual love also reflect each other: the whole universe, from individual human beings to God, is bound up in a single movement. [82] In neither of the other registers is the cosmic dimension tied up with the worldly and human as closely as in sophiology of history. As a matter of fact, in Smysl ljubvi, Solov'ev concluded that this loving interaction goes beyond individuals and extends to social, national and universal collectivity. He characterised it as syzygy [literally from the Greek syzygia, 'yoke'], hereby stressing the aspect of mutual love and autonomy of individuals within the collectivity, and linking the ideal of all-unity with a mystical dimension. [83]

ii) Method: speculation and inspiration

While PH is based on speculative and empirical reason alone, and TH on reason and faith, in SH reason is combined with another instance: inspiration, The expression 'intellectual intuition' that Solov'ev employed to evoke man's contact with the divine world shows that he considered a combination of speculation and inspiration necessary. He used them both in his attempts to present his sophiology in a discursive medium such as in La Sophia, Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve or La Russie et l’Eglise universelle. He also defined the principle or prophecy as the 'freedom of individual inspiration", which shows the central role that he ascribed to this type of knowledge. [84]Although he deals with inspiration and the related notions of intuition and imagination in several passages, he did not elaborate a theory of inspiration, and in his entry 'Vdokhnovenie' [Inspiration] for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, contented himself with mentioning existing positions with respect to this topic. [85] A more explicit relation can be unravelled between his conception of Sophia and his reflections on mysticism. [86] In his early scheme of integral life, he ascribed a significant status to his mystical experience, which shows from his positioning mistika as the highest possible form of creation [see table, p. 12]. Later, in the encyclopaedia entry 'Mistika, misticizm', considering the unmediated communication between the subject and the divine an essential basis (and one which he experienced in his mystical visions), he distinguished between a conception of this communication as the privileged instrument of knowledge above all other devices (mysticism), and one as an essential basis of knowledge (theosophy). [87]

The fact that Solov'ev experienced mystical inspiration is beyond doubt. What remains problematic, however, is the question whether we can speak of a coherent mystical discourse formulated in the many texts in which he expressed this inspiration. Viktorija Kravcenko raises the relevant question of the character and scope [ob "em] of the information that Solov'ev received in mystical trance, and that served as basis for his philosophical reflection. Which part of the information he received was actually worked out and developed? Two problems arise at this point. Firstly, there is almost no trace of the automatic writing fragments in the discursive texts, which suggests that Solov'ev carefully concealed the information that he had received in trance. [88] Secondly, Khoruzij has convincingly pointed out that Solov'ev did not introduce an intermediary stage between inspiration and speculation. The absence of this stage leads to incoherence, and to an 'unpurified' account of the mystical experience. [89] Finally, what distinguishes his discourse from that of other mystics is that he elaborated on God, the world and man, rather than on his personal experience, soul, or spiritual path. [90] In the discursive medium, Solov'ev kept his main source of inspiration concealed and was careful, as it were, not to reveal anything of his own experience.

Solov'ev valued not only speculative knowledge but also the type of knowledge that poets attain through inspiration and intuition. [91] This was exactly what he himself aimed at in his poetry. Indeed he held that the 'clear forms of glory and eternal beauty', are most accessible through 'poetic creation', 'that inner illumination that is called inspiration, through which we may find, even in the actuality of nature, sounds and colours that will embody those ideal types.' [92] One cannot emphasise enough the fact that Solov'ev chose precisely the poetic medium and actively explored it to render his encounters with Sophia. His poetry also expresses his perception of the liveliness of World Soul. On this point, his comment on the lyrical poetry of Fedor Tjutcev is highly instructive. He particularly admired the Russian poet and diplomat for having expressed not only the life of nature, but also the 'actions of World Soul', better than anyone, even Goethe. In storms Tjutcev perceived the deep essence of World Soul, namely chaos and irrationality. He identified life of nature as a fight between light and darkness. Tjutcev did not limit himself to feel nature, but he was also deeply convinced of the objective truth of his view of nature. In this way, 'his mind was completely in accordance with his inspiration.' [93] As a matter of fact, Solov'ev's own poetry contains a form of adoration of the earth, for instance as 'Queen Earth', 'Eve of Turania', Madonna of the steps.' [94] In contemplating nature, the poet witnesses the painful strife of the 'earthly soul' to unite with the 'unearthly world', as well as their fusion. [95] He read in nature, as well as in history as we have seen, the symptoms of the progressive fusion of the world with God, in other terms, of the sophianisation of humanity. His poetry reveals that he understood his own individual mystical fusion with Sophia as part of the same process. [96] In a freer way than was possible in theoretical treatises, this genre allowed him to express a direct relationship with Sophia-World Soul by means of a non-discursive language, the immediacy of which speaks to the senses and the emotions rather than to cerebral cognition. Besides, the freedom inherent to the poetic language enabled him to speak of both the materiality and the spirituality of the experience. and, even belter, to establish an intimate link between these two levels. That he worshipped Sophia, and with her World Soul did not escape his contemporaries, who labelled it as a 'cosmic cult' of the 'earthly Aphrodite' close to paganism. [97] This did not hinder him, however, to fiercely reject the cult of humanity as Comte promote it. [98]

However, poetry was not sufficient to express the ultimate truth. since it expressed only the emotion of the moment, and not eternal truth. [99] It had to be combined with philosophical speculation. In La Sophia, he considered dialectics to be the most adequate means of expressing the most powerful force active in history, the reality of love. [100] By dialectics [see previous chapter], he meant not only a logical device, but also a totalising approach. which enables one to conceive of the unity of all and which seeks to unveil the cosmic process as a whole. [101] Solov'ev understood its main principle as the 'unity of itself and of its opposite.' In this way dialectics can indeed he understood as a translation of love. which unites the self with one's other. into logical thought. This interpretation explains Solov'ev's early fascination for dialectics as the best means of building universal religion. [102] However, the core of dialectics, namely negation and negation of negation, found no real echo in his considerations, which focused rather on the 'union' or 'synthetic' moment of the process. He abandoned this method in his later works on sophiology. Speculation dominates, in the form of abstraction, generalisation and theorisation, sometimes combined with data from physics, biology and psychology. In Smysl ljubvi the philosopher made a unique attempt to combine speculation with the poetic trope of oxymoron and with scientific discourse, in order to express the penetration of the mystical dimension in the material world. He identified light, electricity, magnetism, and warmth as 'weightless matter that penetrates and is penetrated everywhere -- in a word, immaterial matter.' [103] The oxymoron, in which apparently contradictory terms appear in conjunction. was the figure of speech par excellence by which Solov'ev was able to express the combination of spiritual and material typical of sophiology.

e) Actors

i) God, Sophia, and World Soul


From the preceding paragraphs, the role of the actors God, Sophia and World Soul is clearly shown and needs only to be summed up at this point. As far as God is concerned in this register, he plays a major part as the absolute principle and the creator, who loves his creation, which is embodied in its ideal unity in Divine Sophia. This love also is. or at least should be, the central force that animates common man in his activities and interactions with other individuals. with the collectivity, and with nature. Sophia as Divine Wisdom exists prior to creation, and is its model. Besides. she is in contact with man to the extent that she speaks to the poet-prophet. World Soul, the created substratum of all that exists, labours towards its union with God through man and nature.

ii) The prophet

Let us now turn to the last main actor of this register, namely the individual capable of perceiving Sophia-World Soul, that is, the prophet. The prophet is the key figure in the union between God and the world. [104] Solov'ev describes this person as a privileged individual, chosen by Sophia, who receives and picks up her message, and transmits it to his or her contemporaries. These individuals can be philosopher-mystics, such as Bohme, Swedenborg and Schelling, whom Solov'ev mentioned as the creators of the philosophy of soul: he added himself to this list. [105] These can also be poets. In this connection, he elaborated an original conception of prophecy. Although mystic insight and poetic inspiration do not necessarily make a prophet, in Solov'ev' s case mystic experience 'provides a possible foundation and validation for the poet's prophetic status.' [106] Very early on, Solov'ev sought to construct an ideal and tradition of prophecy that could fully legitimate his own experience. He first investigated the well-established Russian literary tradition of the poet-prophet based on the figure of Puskin, and formulated it by choosing Dostoevskij as its initiator. He then turned to a purely religiously based tradition, that of the Hebrew prophets. [107] To this picture we could add Solov'ev' s sustained interest in mysticism, as shown by a whole range of publications on the topic. [108]

Arguably, his sense of prophetic mission took its source in his mystical visions. Revealing in this respect is Solov'ev's view regarding biblical prophecies about Jesus Christ, that 'the unconscious is the distinctive sign of true prophecy.' [109] One can reasonably assume that the dialogue form which he chose for La Sophia reflects for a great part an original mystical experience, in which Sophia reveals the date of her rebirth to the philosopher and others, and instructs him for this purpose to definitively establish universal religion in theory and in practice. The altogether intimate and dependent relationship that Solov'ev enjoyed with Sophia is quite obvious from the following scene transcribed in automatic writing, and in which Sophia commands him:

I am that what you are, I am your essence. You are only my subject, my hypokeimenon -- the thing upon which I lean my feet, my hypostasion, this must be your supreme ambition. But I do not want to put my feet on a vulgar object. This is why you have to work and produce great things. [110]


However, in Solov'ev's eyes, mystic insight and poetic talent were not enough to make somebody a prophet. The true prophet is entrusted with a moral mission, the application of which should start in his own life. This is the reason why Solov'ev praised Polish poet Adam Mickiewicz so highly. Mickiewicz had also had a mystic experience: the Orthodox icon of the Virgin of Czestochowa situated on Polish ground, had appeared to him, indicated the right path to him, and thus saved him. This is a striking reminder of Sophia. The poet had overcome three temptations or forms of exclusive love: sexual love, nationalism, and obedience to the Catholic Church. [111] These heroic deeds made him a superior man, in contrast to Puskin, who, though perhaps the established poet-prophet of the Russian tradition, had not lived according to the higher principles that he had caught a glimpse of. Solov'ev was concerned with the reformulation of the notion of poet-prophet, which had become a cliche by the Puskin commemoration of 1880. In his commemorative speech, Solov'ev emphasised Mickiewicz's concern for moral order. His essential merit had been to indicate paths, without needing to be more specific. These two aspects are also central in Solov'ev's interventions. From this speech it appears that Solov'ev found in Mickiewicz a kindred spirit and the model of the prophet he himself strove to be.

He remoulded the notion of prophecy primarily in his sophiology. Arguably, the prophet is essentially a translator of higher truths, which he has received through sophianic revelation and poetic inspiration into his own life, but also into the social environment in which he lives. Prophecy contained a moral, social, and national dimension that Solov'ev deeply felt to be his mission. [112] Typical for this very peculiar kind of social activism is the combination of solitary action with an interpretation of events from a moral perspective. Solov'ev identified himself with the prophet, who is entitled to playa fundamental role in history, as the authority that anticipates the union of God with the world through moral deeds, reminds the earthly power and society of their moral duty, and guides them towards the right path.

iii) Russian educated society and people

The prophet is the guide of educated society and the people: 'the social life of the people has its theocratic organ in the person of the prophet.' [113] This link which Solov'ev made in his theocratic scheme forms the core of his self-perception as a prophet. While in his interventions he constantly addressed Russian educated society [see all case studies], his exhortations after the tsaricide and during the famine especially aimed to guide his fellowmen towards unification with the simple folk [see case studies I and V]. In the Russian tradition, there was already a notion which expressed that ideal unity, namely that of zemstvo. Rather than referring to the institution of local self-government created in 1860, zemstvo in the Slavophile meaning was the 'force originating in the spiritual unity of the people' as opposed to the state. [114] This was also precisely the term that Solov'ev used in his scheme of free theocracy to mean this unity. [115]

His untiring prophetic commitment can be best explained through his conviction that Russia was bound to embody Sophia on earth. This conviction was seldom expressed, but was nonetheless deep-rooted in his thought. In his eyes, Russians had a special bond with Sophia through their veneration of Wisdom. Solov'ev interpreted this veneration in a messianic perspective:

The Russian people has known and loved, under the name of Holy Sophia, the social incarnation of the Divinity, in universal church. It is to this idea, which has been revealed to the religious feeling of our ancestors, to this truly national and absolutely universal idea that we now have to give a rational expression. The question is to formulate the living Word that ancient Russia has conceived of and that new Russia has to tell to the world. [116]


With this key passage Solov'ev introduced the last part of La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, devoted to a presentation of the idea of free theocracy. This transition reveals the close link between Sophia, Russia and his model of free theocracy: he developed the idea of free theocracy as that 'rational expression' of Sophia, which should be concretely realised by his country and under his guidance.

One last factor confirms the intimate link between Sophia and Russia in Solov'ev's thought. The fundamental feature that I have identified in Solov'ev's sophiology of history, namely mediation, is central to his characterisation of the Slavic peoples in general, and of the Russian people in particular. In his eyes, Russia was destined to act as a people-mediator [narod posrednik] between the divine and the human world in the sense that it would 'not act out of itself, not realise its own business'; in this way it would also mediate on the horizontal level of immanent history and contribute to reconcile the Western and the Eastern civilisations. [117] One necessary condition for this role was that free theocracy be properly announced by the prophet, and the leaders conscious of their role. The case studies show how Solov'ev set upon himself to realise this mission.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 7:51 am

Part 2 of 3

Conclusion

In his sophiology of history, Solov'ev succeeded in bringing to the fore an alternative way of expressing his intuition about history and the relationship between God and the world in terms of mediation. This register provided him with a framework to conceive of Divine Wisdom both in her perfection and in her commitment to the world, and especially to the poet-prophet. It also enabled Solov'ev to render his perception of the world in its materiality and its femininity, as well as in its attraction to God. Combining these two views harmoniously represented a considerable challenge, which Solov'ev achieved perhaps most effectively in his poetry. In his essays, he progressively separated Sophia from World Soul by confining the latter to the world, and exploring the field of aesthetics and philosophy of love to best express it. The process-like character of World Soul and the teleological perspective of the ultimate unification of World Soul, and through her of man and nature with God, playa central role in this register. Although the properly historical aspects of his sophiology are generally not related to specific historical facts and events, they are present, for instance, in his periodisation as well and in his indications of the fundamental task of man. He did connect Sophia with history in three ways: by identifying Sophia from a messianic perspective, that is, as the ideal society to build on earth, by ascribing to Russia the task of realising Sophia concretely, and by setting upon himself the task to guide society towards that goal. In this respect, he demonstrated these points rather in deed than in his theory, where it remained mostly implicit. The case studies will provide clear evidence of his engagement in society.

His experience confirmed his intuition that World Soul was engaged in a process of divinisation. His search for elements that would allow the integration of both views within one system led him to investigate various traditions and thinkers, ranging from the Kabbalah to the late Schelling. The purpose of the next section is to show that he there found many inspiring thoughts and schemes that would influence his sophiology in an enduring manner.

2. The Dialogue

In one of the drafts for La Sophia. Solov'ev writes:

Neoplatonism -- Kaballa / Law / Old Testament
Bohme -- Swedenborg / Gospel / New Testament
Schelling -- Me / Freedom / Eternal Testament [118]


This quote reveals that Solov'ev saw himself as part of a line of a tradition that he felt it was his mission to complete and to crown, The strongest and most enduring sources of inspiration for his sophiology were the Kabbalah, Gnosticism, Bohme, and Schelling. I present and discuss these below in this order.

a) The Kabbalah

The Kabbalah is the main body of Jewish mystical writings, written in the 12th century in Southern France (Provence), and which has been actively elaborated upon since then. [119] A major characteristic of the Kabbalah is that 'God is linked to the world through ten sephirot or hypostatic numbers, These mediate between the Infinite and this world and are one of the functions that help to explain how an entirely ineffable being can produce the amount of variety found in nature.' [120] From this definition, it is clear why the Kabbalah attracted Solov'ev, as it offered a way of conceptualising mediation between God and creation, a central aspect of sophiology, as I have argued above. In addi- tion, the Kabbalah posits the possibility of a personal knowledge of God, attainable through spiritual exercise. Doubtlessly, although he did not elaborate on this topic in his treatment of the Kabbalah, this teaching gave Solov'ev an effective framework that took into account the possibility of a mystical knowledge of God.

The role of Kabbalah in Solov'ev has been comprehensively analysed by Konstantin Burmistrov. [121] Burmistrov convincingly demonstrates the inconsistency of a commonly accepted view: against a general agreement on Solov'ev's study of Kabbalistic sources in the 1870s, especially during his stay in the British museum of London in 1875, there is no evidence that Solov'ev had a direct knowledge of Kabbalistic texts, apart from translations and works of vulgarisation. [122] On the whole, his first encounter with the Kabbalah did indeed bear the stamp of the occultist interpretation of the Kabbalah that was in fashion in his time. [123] At that time, the Kabbalistic influence on his sophiological writings must therefore have been highly limited and reduced to the appropriation of certain terms that he redefined such as 'Eyn Sof [Infinity, as the main attribute of God], 'Adam Kadmon' [Heavenly human being, containing within itself the incarnation of all divine forms], 'Beth Col' [literally 'Daughter of the voice', or divine voice heard by the human being who is in the state of elevation], 'Sephirot' [basic force], 'Shekhinah' [literally 'presence' or 'dwelling', designating the feminine Other of God, his extrinsic manifestation] and schemes combining these categories or characters. [124]

Solov'ev developed his knowledge of the Kabbalah at a later stage, in the 1890s, the result of which we can see in his article on the Kabbalah for the encyclopaedia Brokgauz-Efron, and in his introduction to David Gincburg's article on the Kabbalah published in Voprosy filosofii i psikhologii in 1896. [125] His study of the Kabbalah advanced considerably with his learning Hebrew from the start of the 1880s onwards and his visits to Gincburg, who possessed an impressive collection of Jewish literature, including Kabbalistic manuscripts. [126] His deepened knowledge coincided with his scholarly investigations of the history of Judaism as a whole [see case study III 'The Jewish Question']. Beside his erudition in Hebrew terminology and his historical sense in the scholarly discussion of the difficult issue of the emergence of the Kabbalah, his entry reveals his profound sympathy for the teaching.

Two points are highly significant with respect to the issue of Solov'ev's sophiology of history. Firstly, in this entry, he brought to the fore the peculiar feature of the Kabbalistic conception of God as possessing a feminine Other [Shekhinah]. Shekhinah is 'the feminine aspect of God', and, significantly, in the Kabbalah is sometimes assimilated to the last sephirot, namely Kingdom [Malchut], which, in contrast with the other sephirot, is also feminine. [127] As we have seen above, Solov'ev picked up this significant link between feminine divinity and Kingdom and reinterpreted it in Christian eschatological terms in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle. [128] Secondly, in this entry as a whole, he emphasised the process-like and gradual character of the Kabbalistic scheme. [129]

Summing up, Solov'ev's sustained study of the Kabbalah, which he began in the early 1870s with secondary literature and which he deepened with the analysis of original manuscripts up to the 1890s, testifies to his vivid interest for this complex tradition. This can be explained by the fact that he was inspired by some of its core aspects. Here he found a framework that obviously confirmed his intuition of history, structured on the one hand by the vertical line of ontological hierarchy, the mediation between God and the world through a whole range of onto logically intermediary beings, and, on the other, on the horizontal line of chronology, God's feminine Other as its starting point, and the Kingdom to come as its endpoint. These aspects were totally absent in the theological and philosophical understanding of history. Finally, the Kabbalah involved knowledge by emanation, which could only appeal to Solov'ev, who had experienced mystical visions and took them as a point of departure for his grand system.

b) Gnosticism

In 1875, Solov'ev wrote a prayer to Sophia that contained numerous central Gnostic categories. [130] That Gnostic teachings captured his attention from early on is clearly shown by the fact that he considered writing his doctoral dissertation on gnosis. [131] In fact, another work altogether resulted from these reflections, namely Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, but the influence of Gnosticism remained pregnant under the surface of his works. In scholarship on the influence of Gnosticism on Solov'ev, Aleksej Kozyrev's study stands out as a major work. [132]

Defining Gnosticism is not an easy task. It is divided into various systems, and its origin is still problematic. Most generally speaking, however, Gnosticism refers to the body of teachings of gnosis [the Greek term gnosis meaning literally: knowledge], which arose in the first centuries of Christianity, and which sought to overcome pure faith in order to attain a higher level of knowledge of the mystery of the Christian religion. In this sense, Gnosticism is less a religion than a religious philosophy. Roughly speaking, Gnostic thought is characterised by five main features. Firstly, a radical dualism, with, on the one hand, the transcendent realm of spirit, and, on the other, gross matter. Second, a distinction between absolute divinity, seen as good, and the creator or Demiurge, considered evil. Third, a conception of humans as originating in the higher realm, but which is 'now imprisoned in the form of a soul within the material body.' Fourth, a battle to liberate one's soul from materiality, hence positing a puritan ethic. [133] Fifth and finally, the selective aspect of knowledge, which is available to the initiated few.

The Gnostic cosmogony is original in many respects. In the transcendent realm, divinity is not alone, but surrounded by a wide range of partial expressions of his perfection that emanate from it, the thirty aeons, which together form the pleroma [plenitude]. [134] The last aeon is a female aeon, Sophia, which, out of an excessive desire to know the unknowable divinity, 'is drawn into a history of passion and error that leads her outside the blessed pleroma.' [135] The goal of history is the return of the exiled Sophia into the pleroma, and with her, the whole of creation.

On the basis of Solov'ev's early drafts and the entries he wrote for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia, it is clear from the outset that he had a vivid interest in Gnosticism and was well versed in Gnostic teaching, especially the one developed by theologian Valentinus [around 150 AD]. Solov'ev wrote two texts explicitly on Gnosticism, namely the entries for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia 'Gnosticizm', and 'Valentin i Valentiniany.' [136]

In 'Gnosticizm', Solov'ev showed himself highly critical of the Gnostic body of teachings and denounced the reconciliation that it had made between all elements that true Christianity had sought to reconcile as only 'apparent.' In fact, Solov'ev argued, God and the world remained separated in Gnostic doctrine, contrary to the Christian tradition. [137] Arguably, his exclusively disapproving stance was dictated by the need to avoid censorship on this delicate matter: after all, Gnosticism was judged the heresy par excellence, and the qualification 'Gnostic' equated to 'heretic' in Russia. [138] As a matter of fact, this reaction neither reflects Solov'ev's personal valuation of the Gnostic teaching, nor the tremendous role that Valentinus' thought played in Solov'ev's own intellectual development.

A far more sympathetic tone prevailed in the entry 'Yalentin i Valentiniany', in which Solov'ev presented 'one of the most brilliant thinkers of all times.' [139] Of the description of Valentinus' cosmogony, which he trustfully made on the basis of the canonical authority in this matter, namely Irenaeus of Lyon, the most significant aspect for our discussion is that of the two Sophias. [140] The first or higher Sophia was the last aeon, who wished to know the unknowable God. Frustrated in her desire, she became indeterminate and passive. [141] She was stopped in her strife by encountering the limit, which expelled her infant, also described as 'objectivated passionate desire', from the pleroma and 'reestablished Sophia in her previous place in the pleroma.' This infant, characterised as 'formless' and called 'Achamoth' [Mother], is the second or lower Sophia. [142] She was exiled from the pleroma, fell into an even deeper state of distress and suffering than the first Sophia. She generated first matter [hule], and then the Demiurge, Satan and devils, and other spirits. Without the Demiurge's knowing, she blew a divine seed into the Demiurge's creature, man: 'The goal of the world process consists precisely in that this small spiritual seed opens itself, develops and nourishes itself through the knowledge of the psychic and material things. [... ] The moment all Gnostics know themselves and have developed their spiritual seed, the end of the world will come. Sophia- Achamoth will definitely unite with the Saviour and enter the pleroma; the souls of the Gnostics, which will adopt a feminine aspect, will enter into union [sizigija] with the angels and will also be accepted in the pleroma.' [143]

Solov'ev was eager to integrate these Gnostic elements in his early cosmogony. In La Sophia, we find a three-level scheme consisting of God, Soul or Sophia, and man, and the following narrative; first, the primordial and ultimate all-unity or pleroma; second, a close relationship of the fallen Sophia with the world, which her son the Demiurge creates, and towards the salvation of which she works; and finally her intimate relationship with man, to whom she gives a divine spark, the element necessary to make him elevate himself to gnosis or complete knowledge of God. [144] It was only later, in Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve and La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, that he adopted the conception of the two Sophias, one being (again) part of the pleroma, and the other suffering and working at man's salvation.

In 'Valentin i Valentiniany', which is mostly devoted to a survey of Valentinus' cosmogony, Solov'ev added only one appreciative remark, which is central for our analysis. He acknowledged Valentinus' 'greatest achievement' from a philosophical point of view, namely that of having developed a new view of matter. By overcoming the dualism between matter as an illusion (Indian pantheism and Eleatic philosophers), and matter as an autonomous reality (rest of Greek philosophy [sic, Me]), Valentinus had succeeded in positing matter as a 'conditional reality, namely as a real result of psychic changes.' [145] Solov'ev therefore found a positive valuation of matter in Valentinus' teaching that integrated two elements, namely the relationship of matter to the spiritual, and its participation in the historical process. These are central elements of his thought. However, it seems that by interpreting Valentinus' teaching in this way, Solov'ev twisted it. Worth remembering, indeed, is the Gnostics' view of the world as an omnipresent reign of evil, a view that prompted them to hold this world in contempt. Solov'ev gave Valentinus' conception of matter a distinctly positive turn, which was certainly not the intention of the ancient author.

Can we say that Solov'ev adopted the Gnostic theory of the knowledge of God? It is tempting to typify him as 'Gnostic' or 'pneumatic', the highest category of human being, who, according to the Gnostic teaching, possesses the perfect knowledge in virtue of the spiritual seed that Sophia has placed in them. [146] However, Solov'ev not only claimed gnosis but went further and strove by his deeds to change the state of things. [147] He shared neither their aversion nor contempt for the world, nor their conception of a radically transcendent and distant God. In contrast, he used the figure of Sophia to bridge the gap between God and the world, and assumed their narrative on the divine origin of matter precisely in order to integrate it into his own narrative on the spiritualization of matter.

The most obvious traces of Gnosticism can be found in La Sophia. The more Solov'ev reworked his cosmogony, the more he purged it of obvious Gnostic allusions, and put to the foreground a neutral philosophical apparatus and orthodox Christian terminology. The gradual disappearance of overt Gnostic terminology (pleroma, aeons, Achamoth, Demiurge, to name the most important) does not mean, however, that Solov'ev completely distanced himself from Gnosticism. In his sophiology proper, I agree with Kozyrev that Solov'ev never turned his back on the Gnostic teaching. For instance, he returned to the Gnostic cosmogonic myth in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle. [148] Moreover, in my eyes, passages in Opravdanie dobra on the spiritualization of matter bear Gnostic features. Another aspect is Valentinus' positive valuation of heterosexual intercourse and marriage as a symbol of the sacred marriage of the aeons or syzygy. [149] The myth, presented by Plato and remoulded by Valentinus, that man and woman together reflect divine androgyny was completed, in Solov'ev's sophiology, by another erotic relationship, namely that between Divine Wisdom and the poet-prophet, and by extension to the social organism. [150]

Fifteen hundred years earlier, Valentinus had advocated a 'Christianity with a mystic and philosophical orientation', and combined within his cosmogony two feminine figures, that of higher Sophia and that of lower Sophia. [151] His thought doubtlessly lay close to the ambition of the Russian philosopher, who picked up these two categories, in which he found an echo of his own perception of Sophia-World Soul.

c) Bohme

The decisive influence of the German mystic and theosophist Jacob Bahme (1575-1624) on Solov'ev's sophiology has long been acknowledged. [152] The theosophist allowed him to deepen one fundamental aspect of his sophiology, namely Divine Wisdom as the feminine figure of Sophia. Bohme provided Solov'ev with a category of Sophia that suited many of the Russian philosopher's aspirations, by relating her to God, to humanity, and to history. Whereas Valentinus and the Kabbalah had provided the metaphysical framework for his sophiology, Solov'ev found in Bohme a first attempt to anchor Sophia in the properly Christian tradition, and to enrich the conception of her role in history in particular.

Solov'ev first entered the world of German mysticism in the early 1870's through salons, in particular that of Sofija Tolstaja, and through the academic milieu. [153] In the years 1875- 1877, Solov'ev deepened his knowledge of theosophical literature, especially of Jacob Bohme, Emmanuel Swedenborg (1688-1772), and their predecessor Paracelsus (1493- 541). [154] During this two-year period, he came to identify his ecstatic visions of divine Sophia with the gottliche Sophia of Bohme's theology and cosmology. From then on, even though we do not have many references to Bohme at our disposal, according to Solov'ev's own testimony his religious and philosophical views paralleled the crucial insights of the Bohmist school. [155]

In contrast to the traditional definition of God as pure being and opposed to the pure becoming characteristic for the world, Bohme developed an alternative conception of God that took into account opposition and becoming. He stated that God poses himself and opposes within himself his own contrary being in order to develop a clear consciousness and possession of himself, and to absorb the infinity of partial disharmonies in a harmonious synthesis. [156] Bohme's conception of Sophia is central to his thought, which he however did not develop into a system. Alexandre Koyre has brought to the fore the multiple facets and at the same time the unity of B5hme's idea of eternal Wisdom:

It [the idea of Eternal Wisdom, MC] is -- and that is what informs the unity of the conception -- the eternal Objectum, the Gegenwurf of God in which and through which he reflects, expresses and reveals himself. It follows, as it were, the immanent evolution of God, transforming itself at each stage which this evolution has reached; it makes an emanating evolution for God possible. It is thus a necessary condition of this evolution and at the same time, an intermediary between God and nature. It is also, for nature, the ideal image which it [... ] realises or tends to realise. It is its eternal goal. its Vorbild, its idea. [157]


This quote clearly shows that in Bohme's view, it is not only Wisdom that evolves, but God also, precisely through Wisdom. Besides, Wisdom functions as an intermediary between God and nature, and as an ideal for the latter. Solov'ev closely followed Bohme in the following points: Sophia as the 'essence of God, as the ideal nature of the world, and as the instrument of human salvation.' [158] Firstly, Solov'ev agreed with the link made by Bohme between Sophia and God. Bohme defined this link in terms of manifestation and revelation: Sophia, as God's essence and essential wisdom, is the first revelation and objectivation of the divine thought. [159] Sophia emanates as the result of the struggle within God of two poles, the 'One' and 'prime matter' or 'Centre of nature.' [160] The One gradually overcomes prime matter and shapes it into Sophia, according to a primeval master plan [the 'Eternal Idea']' Furthermore, in Bohme, Sophia is related to the persons of the Trinity as follows: 'The loci of powers with which the One transforms prime matter into Sophia are the Persons of the Trinity. [... ] Sophia thus becomes the embodiment of all the potentialities of the Trinity.' [161] Exactly the same formulation can be found in Solov'ev's La Russie et l’Eglise universelle. [162]

Secondly, in elaborations on the relationship between Sophia, man and the world, Solov'ev follows Bohme. Before him, the German thinker had found a confirmation of his view of Sophia as God's plan for the world or 'heavenly humanity' in the Old Testament texts on Divine Wisdom. [163] Just as the world is a projection of Sophia in nature, man is a reproduction of Sophia. But since the fall of man and the world, both have ceased to be Sophia's image, and have instead become subject to Sophia's rival, which Bohme called Seele der grussen Welt, Geist dieser Welt [soul of the big world, spirit of this world]. [164] However, the point of rivalry is not a constant view in Solov'ev's work. [165] The Russian philosopher came to this view of World Soul in opposition to Sophia in later reflections, as we have seen, at the end of the 1880s in La Russie et l'Eglise universelle, but not before.

Thirdly, Solov'ev shared with Bohme the idea that the future would bring about the 'rehabilitation of the world from its current fallen state as a gradual reincarnation of Sophia through man.' [166] In La Russie et l'Eglise universelle, we do indeed see how Solov'ev, following Bohme, identified particular manifestations of Sophia in the Virgin Mary and in Jesus Christ, a logical extension of which would be Sophia's incarnation in humanity as a whole, once it will have absorbed World Soul. [167] It seems therefore that Bohme had a vivid sense of Sophia standing both at the beginning of history, as humanity's model, and at its end, as its ideal. Incontestably, Solov'ev was happy to find a framework in Bohme that enabled him to translate his own intuition about the role of Sophia for the destiny of humanity.

It is relevant, however, to point out significant differences between the two theosophists, and not to take Solov'ev as a Bohmist, as David at some points suggests. Solov'ev found useful means of attaining a greater stage of conceptuality of Sophia in the German theosophist. However, he later abandoned these or openly rejected them. Firstly, Solov'ev explicitly disagreed with Bohme's admittance of an element of chance and arbitrariness in history. [168] Secondly, after having adopted the German theosophist's idea that God struggles with his opposite [in Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija], he abandoned it and privileged a narrative in which God is only unity and plenitude [in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle]. [169] Other differences must be mentioned specifically regarding Sophia. The Bohmian Sophia is essentially the Eternal Virgin, whereas for Solov'ev Sophia possesses a highly erotic character and is distinct from the Virgin. [170] Solov'ev also actively thematised his personal relationship with this Divine feminine figure, whereas such an intimate relationship did not appear at all in Bohme's texts. [171] The Bohmian Sophia was after all not feminine, not erotic, and not personal, in contrast with Solov'ev's Sophia. Besides, the 17th century mystic and Solov'ev quite logically did not share the same worldview, which can be reflected in their sophianic conceptions: Solov'ev's was far more penetrated with the nineteenth-century ideas of progress than Bohme's was. [172] He also ascribed a far more active role to man and humanity in incarnating Sophia than Bohme did, and consequently, placed far greater emphasis on humanity as the main actor in history. The Russian philosopher nevertheless found inspiration in Bohme for his definition of Sophia in relationship to God, and as both the ideal of history and the means of attaining it.

d) Schelling

Testimony of Solov'ev's profound admiration for Schelling is found in a draft in which the twenty-year old philosopher stated that 'Schelling is the true ancestor of universal religion.' [173] At about the same time, Solov'ev studied the positive philosophy of Schelling, and in particular assumed the conception of the Absolute for its intimate connection with nature in its materiality and its femininity. [174] It is precisely this aspect that forms the cornerstone of Solov'ev's sophiology of history.

By the 1840s, German philosopher Friedrich Schelling (1755- 1854) had become a central figure in Russian thought. [175] The similarity between Solov'ev's philosophy and that of Schelling therefore did not escape the attention of his contemporaries. [176] But reflecting on the Schellingian thought often amounted to being perceived as a pantheist, at least in the Orthodox Christian circles to which Solov'ev wanted to belong. Arguably, this explains why Solov'ev preferred not to mention this source in his works. He made explicit references to the German philosopher extremely rarely in fact. Nevertheless, Schelling's role in Solov'ev's work has hardly ever been contested: with the notable exception of Losev, all commentators conclude to a direct influence of the German idealist on the Russian thinker. [177] More specifically, Schelling as a source of inspiration for Solov'ev's sophiological writings was already detected by Bulgakov, and recently examined by Paul Valliere. [178] It seems relevant to affirm that Schelling provided the first theoretical impulse for Solov'ev's sophiology. [179] As far as sophiology of history is concerned, Schelling played a major role with respect to two central points, first, the emphasis on the value of matter and nature, and, second, a newly defined link between nature and God.

According to Bulgakov, Schelling, and after him Solov'ev, had the immense merit of elevating the ontological significance of matter, and of transferring the observation of nature into the field of philosophical investigation. [180] This 'religious materialism' had dominated Christian thought from the ecumenical councils onwards. The tradition was broken, however, with the rise of rationalism in Western thought, which considered nature purely in mechanistic and causal terms. It was only with Schelling that the metaphysical link between man and nature was restored through a consideration of nature as God's living creation. [181] He reanimated the concept of World Soul for this purpose. Solov'ev knew about this, and considered Schelling to be the last of a long tradition of authors from Plato to Goethe who had dealt with World Soul. [182] The question then whether Solov'ev borrowed the concept from Schelling. In order to answer this question, we must first turn to Schelling's elaborations.

The German philosopher's views evolved considerably during the course of his life. First, in his treatise Uber die Weltseele (1798), he defined World Soul as 'an eternal and infinite willing-of-itself [... ] in all forms, grades, and potencies of reality', an 'organising principle developing the world as a system. Perhaps the ancients wished to indicate [such a principle] with the world Soul.' [183] Later, in Philosophie und Religion (1804), he rejected the theory of emanation that dominated his philosophy of nature, and advocated the need for a leap between the Absolute and the world, which he introduced with the notion of fall. [184] In his Einleitung in die Philosophie der Mythologie (1842, 1847-52, published posthumously) he defined World Soul as 'that what God is and at the same time is different from him. She is the mediator [Vermittlerin], who leads the divided and material being to eternal unity.' [185] Here World Soul is defined as a mediator between the material and the divine. If we look into his lectures on the philosophy of revelation (Philosophie der Offenbarung, given in Berlin in 1841-2 and published posthumously), we observe that the concept has disappeared, but, interestingly, that the Old Testament idea of Wisdom is mentioned. In the history of religion, the idea of Wisdom succeeded that of Weltamme [upokeimenon]. It is in the Proverbs ascribed to Solomon that the original potency [Urpotenz] is the most precisely described, as 'Chochmah', as 'subject, prius, supposition of all future movement, that which communicates to the Creator his knowledge of future movement.' [186] Wisdom is thus closely involved in God's creation of movement. However, Schelling did not elaborate on a possible link of succession between Wisdom and World Soul.

As far as Solov'ev's treatment of Schelling is concerned, the five following aspects are significant. Firstly, he welcomed the fact that Schelling had recognised the reality of the material feminine principle, without which, Solov'ev added, there is no process. [187] Second, like Schelling, he ascribed two main qualities to World Soul, namely unity and life. Third, he also identified World Soul with the material principle or upokeimenon of our world, which is the term with which Schelling designated the substratum of future creation. [188] Fourth, he also distinguished Divine Sophia from World Soul. And finally, Schelling's description of Wisdom on the basis of Solomon's Proverbs can be found in Solov'ev's La Russie et l'Eglise universelle. There is therefore a similarity of evolution of thought, and a terminological and, to a certain extent, conceptual correspondence.

We cannot however speak of direct borrowing. As a matter of fact, in Solov'ev's work, World Soul is defined essentially as the link between the divine and the human, whereas in Schelling's thought, apart from in his Einleitung in die Philosophie der Mythologie, World Soul is mainly the foundation, Ungrund of nature. [189] Perhaps, it was this definition that Solov'ev had in mind when he criticised Schelling's emphasis on the 'absolute and arbitrary worldly force.' [190] With this view of World Soul as Ungrund, he seemed to identify Schelling's Weltseele with that of Schopenhauer. However, Solov'ev explicitly rejected Schopenhauer's definition of World Soul as a blind, impersonal will, which was subject to no higher power, and which thus did not suppose the existence of God. [191] In this sense, he used Schelling in his position against Schopenhauer. I would like to suggest yet another difference. The early Schelling emphasised World Soul's battle towards unity, and her simultaneous will to separate herself from God, and made this opposition between unity and conflict central to his conception. [192] By contrast, Solov'ev preferred not to make these two battles coincide in his cosmogony, but posited them as alternating with each other: after a period of revolt and conflict, World Soul had striven to return to the divine. [193]

Solov'ev was not only inspired by the regained ontological status of matter that Schelling had provided, but also by the new link between matter and God, which follows from it. Against the ontological distinction between God and nature that had become dominant, especially since the triumph of rationalism, Schelling strove to conceptualise a close link between the two. He provided the logical apparatus of this conceptualisation with his theory of the potencies [Potenzlehre]. [194] The life of the absolute can be distinguished into a first potency (indeterminate ground of being or pure possibility), a second potency (of determinate being or pure actuality or positing of the other), and a third potency of overcoming the alienation between the first and the second, or harmonisation between the two. [195] Schelling thereby situated identity and opposition in the core of being, and thus also in God. This allowed him to introduce nature in God, which was precisely what Solov'ev sought, in order to provide World Soul with a maximal ontological status, and to conceptualise his intuition of the intimate connection between World Soul and the divine.

In Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, Solov'ev adopted two significant moments of the Potenzlehre, that of God's positing his other, and the view that the idea has two lives, one in the absolute, and one in itself, separated from the absolute. [196] At this stage, Solov'ev distinguished within the Absolute two poles, the first absolute or all-united being, and the second absolute or all-unity in becoming. This second pole is necessary to the Absolute to the extent that 'the Absolute cannot exist in reality otherwise than realised in its other.' [197] 'Next to the absolute being [absoljutno suscij] [... ], we have to admit another essence [suscestvo] which is just as absolute, but which at the same time is not identical with the absolute as such'; It 'progressively becomes all- united'; 'possesses the divine element, all-unity, as its eternal potency, which gradually turns into reality.' [198] The following step is crucial for our analysis: 'this essence, in its relative being, represents two elements: the divine idea [... ] as the form of all-unity, and the material element, the perceivable plural natural being'; 'this second absolute [... ] being in this quality the World Soul' perceives itself first in man: 'in the extra-human world of nature the divine element of World Soul, all-unity, exists only potentially, in a blind, unconscious strife. [199]

Judging from these quotations, Solov'ev assumed Schelling's Potenzlehre. Notably at stake was the possibility of suppressing the dualism of God and nature, and of spirit and matter. Indeed: 'The supernatural divine being [suscestvo] needs nature for the manifestation of its divinity.' [200] In his poetry and his aesthetics, Solov'ev claimed to see in nature a strife towards the divine. Basing himself on Schelling, he conceptualised this link between World Soul and the divine through the theory of the two essences of the absolute. Solov'ev constructed his whole history of religion on this basis? [201] However, there was a limitation to Schelling's influence. This is a point that returns recurrently with respect to Schelling, Bohme, and Hegel, namely that the negativity of being and of the world posited by these thinkers, is nearly absent in Solov'ev. [202]

Schelling's influence on Solov'ev's sophiology was crucial at the early stage of elaboration. Solov'ev picked up Schelling's positive valuation of nature, the concept of World Soul, and the ontological connection of World Soul to God as his second absolute. Later, as we have seen, he abandoned this conception of the absolute probably because it was unacceptable from the theological point of view.

To summarise, Solov'ev drew from currents of thought which offered ways of overcoming the traditional chasms -- between rational knowledge and mystical contemplation, between the divine and the natural, between good and evil, between being and becoming -- elements which he temporarily integrated into his sophiology. From the Kabbalah he borrowed the conception of God's feminine Other (Shekhinah) for his definition of Sophia, as well as the notion of Malkhout or ideal Kingdom, which he integrated into his eschatological view of history, and also, in his early writings, the ontological intermediaries which inhabited the distance between God and the world. A crucial structural element of his scheme was the Gnostic idea of two Sophias: the Valentinian tradition equally stressed a point that Solov'ev had experienced himself, namely a mystical, personal knowledge of God, on the basis of a divine spark or seed that man has to develop. As far as the positive valuation of matter is concerned, it was not central to Gnosticism, as Solov'ev alleged, but rather to Bohme, and later, in a more thoroughly worked out form, to Schelling. From Bohme, Solov'ev took inspiration to combine his idea of Sophia with the Christian tradition, and to define her as the essence of God, to unravel her relationship with the world, and to establish her at the horizon of history, at its glorious end. In Schelling, finally, Solov'ev found a solid conceptual framework in the Potenzlehre, which enabled him to include change in God, to positively value nature, and to place World Soul at a higher ontological level than the Christian tradition had ever done.

Conclusion

Solov'ev's mystical visions of Sophia, together with his perception of World Soul in nature, form the core of his sophiology of history. He sought a way to express in a discursive manner his intuition that World Soul and Sophia were two sides of the same coin by conceptualising the bringing together of man and the divine through World Soul on the model of Sophia. In this sense, mediation is central in the definition of sophiology of history, in contrast with theology of history, which emphasises the ontological distance between the transcendent God of Christianity and the world, and in contrast with philosophy of history, which focuses on the world, regardless of the transcendent level. Mediation is also the central characteristic of the mission of the prophet Solov'ev, who translated eternal truth into the situation hic et nunc, and with this message attempted to guide his fellow countrymen so that they could form a cohesive society. Finally, his interventions found their motivation in his belief that the Russian people possessed the qualities to be the mediator between heaven and earth and to realise Sophia concretely.

Sophiology of history draws from the two 'traditional' registers in the sense that it integrates the dimension of the divine, which forms the core of theology of history, and combines it with the dimension of process, which is central to philosophy of history. However, this combination amounts to an enrichment of the two registers with categories that did not fit into them. The goal of sophiology of history entails the ideal of theology of history, humanity of God, but goes beyond it by including nature and matter, art and sexual love. In the same way, it entails and overcomes the ideal of philosophy of history, all-unity, for the same reasons, and by putting at its core the spiritual dimension absent in that register. Even though Solov'ev did not work out these views in a comprehensive work, and only opened the way for this new register on history, it is precisely the fruitful mediation between the material and the spiritual, between the personal and the cosmic, in a process- like scheme which generates the specificity of his sophiology of history, and a challenging response to traditional worldviews. In the second part of my research I show on which occasions and with which means Solov'ev sought to transform Russia so that it could lie at the basis of a concrete incarnation of Sophia.

_______________

Notes:

1. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 131, transl. p. 131.

2. Written as a comment to his own poem 'Tri svidanija', SS. 12, p. 86.

3. Scholars haw pointed out that Solov'ev's 'erotic utopia' or Sophia is not less central to his thought than his ‘theocratic utopia' (Leonid Heller, Michel Niqueux. Histoire de l’utopie en Russie (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1995), p. 161.

4. Kline 1974, p, 159.

5. I will come to a more specific characterisation at the end of the following paragraph, after analysing the notion of Sophia-World Soul.

6. One can indeed speak of Solov'ev's 'lifelong devotion to Sophia' (for a sensible portrait of the philosopher, see Nicolas Zernov, Three Russian Prophets: Khomiakov, Dostoevsky, Soloviev (London: S.C.M. Press, 1944), quotation from p. 128). From here onwards, I use the personal pronouns 'she' and 'her' to designate Sophia-World Soul, in order to emphasise the personal relationship that Solov'ev entertained with this figure. As a matter of fact, Sophia-World Soul not only fulfilled the function of a metaphysical principle in Solov'ev's thought, but is also his interlocutor, inspiration and beloved. Sophia's physical presence is indicated in his work La Sophia in which Sophia speaks to the philosopher through her eyes. her words. and her gestures (p. 80). As far as World Soul is concerned, he qualified this being as a 'living being with aspirations. representations and feelings’ ('Mirovaja dusa', SS. 10. p, 246). and is therefore also treated as a person.

7. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve (op. cit.): I translate mirovaja dusa as 'World Soul' and not 'the world soul' as the translator does, to emphasise the role or this entity as a concrete figure, as it were, in Solov'ev's perception. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, op. cit: Smysl ljubvi, first published in 1894. Edition used: Vladimir Solov'ev. S. 1998 2. pp. 493-547.

8. A portion of his poems was published during his life in journals. Edition used: SS. 12. English translation: Vladimir Solovyov's Poems of Sophia, Boris Jakim and Laury Magnus (transl. intr. notes) (New Haven, Connecticut: The Variable Press. 1996).

9. It is relevant to make a distinction between his sophiology or history, which is the subject matter of this analysis, and his sophiology of love and nature.

10. La Sophia, first published in 1978, republished with the addition of the Russian translation in PSS. 2. pp. 8-160: n. p. 78.

11. La Sophia, p. 150.

12. Solov’ev was perhaps 'the first Russian sophiologist" (Sergei Bulgakov, Sophia the Wisdom of God: An Outline of Sophiology, Rev. Patrick Thompson. Rev. O. Fielding Clarke, and Xenia Braitevitc (transl.) (1st publ. 1937; Hudson, New York: Lindisfarne Press, 1993) p. 9). Solov'ev's followers Sergej Bulgakov and Pavel Florenskij developed sophiology in different directions, however, so that it is difficult to find a definition that applies to them all. Bulgakov defined sophiology as proceeding from the 'relation between God and the world, or, what is practically the same thing, between God and humanity' (Ibid., p. 14 [italics Bulgakov's]). Pavel Florenskij defined Sophia even more within the clerical Orthodox conceptual framework with his clearly ecclesiological and Marian understanding of her (Thomas Schipflinger, Sophia-Maria: A Holistic Vision of Creation (York Beach, Maine: Samuel Weiser Inc., 1998). p. 266). In present scholarship. Aleksej Kozyrev considers sophiology as focussing on 'the problem or the mutual relationships of God and the world, and on the origin or the imper- fect world from the perfect God' (A.P. Kozyrev, 'Sofiologija', in: M.A. Maslin (ed.). Russkaja filosofija: Slovar' (Moskva: Respublika, 1995), pp. 465-469: p. 465). According to Paul Valliere, sophiology consists or a 'reflection on the humanity of God as intimated in the cosmicising, transformative works or human culture' (Paul Valliere, 'Sophiology as the Dialogue of Orthodoxy with Modern Civilization', in: Kornblatt and Gustavson 1996, p. 182). The definitions provided by Kozyrev and Valliere are only partially applicable to Solov'ev. They rather express the common denominator or sophiology and Christian tradition than Solov'ev's original contribution or challenge of sophiology with respect to the Christian tradition.

13. Two classic works on Solov'ev's thought have already paved the way for the study or Solol'ev's sophiology: Stremooukhoff 1974, and Losev 2000. Other publications that address the topic are: Paul M. Allen. Vladimir Soloviev: Russian Mystic (Blauvelt, New York: Steiner books, 1978): Samuel 1). Cioran, Vladimir Solov'ev and the Knighthood of the Divine Sophia (Waterloo. Ontario: Wilfred Laurier University Press, 1977). The following recent publications are also highly valuable: Wendy Helleman. 'The World-Soul and Sophia in the Early Work of Vladimir Solov'ev', in: van den Bereken et al. 2000. pp. 163-184: Sergej Khoruzij, 'Nasledie Vladimira Solov'eva sto let spustja', Zurnal moskovskoj patriarkhii, 2000. 11. pp. 69-84: Aleksej Kozyrev, 'Paradoksy nezaversennogo traktata: k publikacii francuzskoj rukopisi Vladimira Solov'eva 'Sofija'", Logos 2 (1991), pp. 152-170: Robert Slesinski. 'Sophiology as a Metaphysics of Creation according to Solov'ev'. in: van den Bercken et al. 2000. pp. 131-146. Specifically on World Soul, see Madey 1961.

14. 'Tri svidanija', SS. 12. pp. 80-86. Of course this poem, like any other writing on his visions, cannot he taken as a direct, unfiltered description of his mystical experience, but is the fruit of a selection and formulation that are well thought through. For an analysis for his poem, see Michel Grabar, 'Les rencontres avec la Sophia: Une experience erotique et mystique de Vladimir Solov'ev', in: van den Bercken et al. 2000. pp. 147-162.

15. La Sophia, p. 74. The three worlds in question are the divine, the ideal, and the natural world (Ibid., p, 48).

16. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 108, transl. p. 108, Solov'ev indeed distinguished between two types of unity in the sphere of the absolute: that which produces (Logos), and that which is produced (Sophia) (Ibid.). By this, he sought to offer an alternative concept of Sophia to the traditional Christian, foremost Byzantine, identification of Sophia either with Logos, or with the Holy Spirit.

17. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 113. transl. p. 113.

18. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p, 249. From the point of view or Orthodox theology, his reflections on Sophia in relation to the hypostases can be considered 'false dogmatics' (Khoruzij 2000, p. 79). For a similar opinion, see Ivan Andreev, 'Vladimir Solov'ev: mistik v svete pravoslavija', Pravoslavnyj put', 1950, 1. pp. 159-172.

19. 'This universal substance, this absolute unity, is the essential wisdom of God (Khocmah, Sophia)' (Ibid.). The spelling is different in English (Chochmah) and in French (Khocmah).

20. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 259 [italics mine].

21. For convincing argumentation on this point, see Sergej Khoruzij, 'Pereput'ja russkoj sofiologii', Novaja Rossija, 1997, 1. pp. 122-130: p. 126. That Solov'ev, though, was inspired by the specifically iconographical tradition, has been shown by Michel Grabar, who has drawn interesting parallels between Sophia's apparitions to Solov'ev in the poem 'Tri svidanija' and the Byzantine tradition (Grabar 2000, pp, 153 -154). Recent literature on the veneration of Premudrost' includes: Elena Mitina, Kategorija mudrosti v drevnerusskom religioznom soznanii (PhD thesis Moskva: Moskovskij gosudarstvennyj universitet, 2001). A recent anthology of texts on Sophia/Virgin is Schipflinger 1998.

22. Solov’ev broached this issue in passing in La Sophia (pp. 152-154), and twenty years later devoted to it his Smysl ljubvi.

23. See 'Tri svidanija', op. cit.

24. ‘U caricy mocj …’ (SS. 12. p. 12). 'Prometeju' (Ibid., p. 92); 'Das ewig-weiblichte’ (Ibid., p. 72).

25. La Sophia, p. 60. The expression 'World Soul" [mirovaja dusa] can be found in the tradition of Western philosophy, from Plato [psykhe tou kosmou] up to Schelling [Weltseele]. Solov'ev devoted to it an entry for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia ('Mirovaja dusa', SS 10, p. 246).

26. Interestingly, Solov’ev again offered an alternative treatment of the Christian topic of the fall. Similar to his theology of history, he did not integrate it into the biblical story of the fall of, but, firstly, made World Soul the subject of fall, and, secondly, placed this event prior to the creation of human beings (Muller 1951, pp. 93-123).

27. La Sophia, p. 130. The identity of the terms ‘Sophia’ and ‘Soul’ in this text can be noted for instance on p. 142 and 150.

28. La Sophia, p. 128.

29. Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, PSS. 3, pp. 285-289. On the influence of Schelling on this point, see subsection Bd). Against Valliere’s view that the expression ‘second absolute’ comes from the 20th-century historian of philosophy Frederick C. Copleston, we can confirm that Solov’ev did use it himself (Ibid., p. 285) (Paul Valliere. ‘Solov’ev and Schelling’s Philosophy of Revelation’, in: van den Bercken et al. 2000, pp. 119-129 [abbreviated Valliere 200b], p. 125, n. 21).

30. About this divine element or principle, other texts suggest that it is an entity that exists apart from, and not within. World Soul, though interacting with it (ex.: Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 136)
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 7:52 am

Part 3 of 3

31. Kritika otvleeennykh nacal, p. 286.

32. The terms all-unity and humanity or God are used in Ibid., p. 295 and 289.

33. Solov’ev wrote about 'world soul or ideal humanity (Sophia), which contains within itself and unites within itself all particular living entities, or souls. As the realisation of the divine principle, its image and likeness, archetypal humanity, or World Soul, is both one and all. World Soul occupies a mediating position between the multiplicity of living entities, which constitute the real content of its life, and the absolute unity of Divinity, which is the ideal principle and norm of its life. [...] It is a dual being' (Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 131. transl. pp. 131- 132 [italics mine]). Another fact points to a certain identity of Sophia and World Soul at this stage. Solov'ev defined World Soul in the same terms as Sophia, as 'passive unity.' Like Sophia, World Soul was a complementary, passive entity to the active divine principle (Ibid.). Sergej Bulgakov further explored this line: 'remaining one, Sophia exists in two modes, eternal and temporal, divine and creaturely' (Bulgakov 1993, p. 74).

34. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 131, transl. p. 131. Another expression used is that of 'middle term or uniting link' (Ibid., p. 120, transl. p. 121).

35. This criticism was not spared him. Trueckoj tried to defend Solove'ev's views against this it (Trubeckoj 1995 1. pp. 111-117).

36. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 257, 254. In a panentheistic vein, Solov'ev argued that, since nothing can exist outside God, 'the extra-divine world cannot but be the divine world, subjectively transposed and turned upside down', the 'subject' of which is World Soul (p. 254). The philosopher nevertheless preserved a link between Sophia and World Soul, which he did not further explicate: 'World Soul exists in God in the state of pure potency, as hidden basis of eternal Wisdom' (Ibid., p. 254) .

37. Ibid., p. 254.

38. About Solov'ev's position with respect to Schopenhauer, von Hartmann, and Schelling, see Kochetkova 2001, pp. 71-100.

39. Smysl ljubvi, pp. 533-534.

40. Judith Deutsch Kornblatt, 'Solov'ev's Androgynous Sophia and the Jewish Kabbalah', Slavic Review 50 (1991), 3. pp. 487-496: p. 495.

41. 'Krasota v prirode’(1889) (S. 1988 2. pp. 351-389). 'Obscij smysl iskusstva' (1889) (S. 1988 2. pp. 390-404). In the definition he gave in the entry 'Priroda', he tended to identify nature and matter ('Priroda', SS. 10. pp. 260 263).

42. 'Krasota v prirode’, p. 388.

43. Ibid., p. 358. English translation in Wozniuk 2003, ‘Beauty in Nature’, pp. 29-60; p. 35. Perhaps his considerations on the link between matter and spiritual principles were inspired by Swedenborg, who developed a theory of correspondences between the natural world and the spiritual world. Solov’ev briefly describes this theory in his entry on the Swedish thinker (‘Svedenborn’, SS. 10, pp. 187-497: p. 490).

44. See ‘Obscij smysl iskusstva’, p. 390 ff. This definition, followed by a brief classification of the arts, echoes Solov’ev’s early hierarchical definition of technical arts, beaux-arts and mysticism as parts of ‘integral creativity’ (Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija, pp. 194-195).

45. Ibid., p. 198.

46. Opravdanie dobra, p. 428.

47. Ibid.

48. This also applies to his aesthetic and ethical writings, although he broached the issue far more ‘in passing’.

49. This definition is inspired by Boris Broys’ enlightening essay (Groys 1995, esp. pp. 37- 40).

50. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, pp. 135-136. For the following account, I base myself on Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve and La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, thereby leaving La Sophia aside as this text, which remained at the stage of a draft, presents too many competing schemes to be coherent.

51. This narrative, which offered an alternative to the traditional biblical scenario, contains strong Gnostic and Kabbalistic accents, which will be examined below. As to the notion of Demiurge, it can already be found in Plato’s Timaeus.

52. Ex.: Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 131, La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 260.

53. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 260 [italics mine]. World Soul is indeed composed of nature and divinity.

54. Ibid. See also Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 135.

55. This survey is based on La Sophia, pp. 54-66 and 116-151, Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, pp. 133-172, La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, pp. 259-297.

56. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 127. In his opinion, there was originally therefore only one divine principle. This thesis equated to posing not polytheism at the origin of religious consciousness, as is usually admitted in the history of religions, but monotheism. This was clearly the objective of his very first work, written in 1873, ‘Mifologiceskij process v. drevnem jazycestve’ (PSS. 1, pp. 17-37).

57. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, pp. 137-138, transl. pp. 139-140.

58. The terminology is somewhat ambiguous. In La Sophia and La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, Solov’ev referred to the cosmic process as the first phase: in Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, the expression ‘cosmic process’ means the entire process, embracing the cosmological, theogonic, and historical ones: in Smysl ljubvi, the ‘cosmic process’ is equated with ‘the physical process’, and thus excludes human history. In Smysl ljubvi V, iii. we find a similar interpretation of the law of gravitation.

59. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 139, transl. p. 141.

60. Ibid.

61. Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 145, La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 276, Solov’ev presented the same treatment of these three cultures in La Sophia (pp. 60, 136-140) and in La Russie et l’Eglise universelle (pp. 273-280): these world-views were successively dominated by cosmic principles, namely by the Spirit in Buddhist and Hindu civilization, by Intelligence in Greek philosophy, and by Soul in the Hebrew religion. One difference between the two texts is that, in La Sophia, these developments already belong to the third, historical phase. In Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve he described the two first stages differently: humanity first worshipped the stars, then the sun and the earthly organic or phallic principle (Shiva, Dionysus), and finally a personal God, which better corresponds to World Soul’s battle for inner unity (Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 144).

62. Ibid., p. 145, transl. p. 147.

63. ‘The liberation of the human self-consciousness and the gradual spiritualization of humanity through the inner assimilation and development of the divine principle constitute the properly historical process of humanity’ (Ibid.).

64. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 265.

65. In Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve this periodisation was reformulated in terms referring to the life of Christ, namely as a temptation of evil on the spirit, mind, and soul of humanity (Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, pp. 162-166). In La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, he was more concerned with reattaching his theory of Sophia to Christology and ecclesiology, and, to a lesser extent, to Mariology, and thus abandoned this periodisation. He indeed elaborated on the three manifestations of ‘Incarnate Sophia’ in Jesus Christ, Mary and the church (La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, pp. 265, 280-297).

66. La Sophia, p. 150. About the influence of Bohme and Schelling on Solov’ev’s sophiology, see subsection 2c and 2d.

67. Ibid., p. 150.

68. La Sophia, p. 167.

69. La Sophia, p. 54. This periodisation and characterization of phases is maintained in Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija, even if the cosmic principles have disappeared from the picture. Solov’ev formulated another periodisation on the basis of the action of several intermediary beings, namely genies, souls, and the spirit of the dead. Interestingly, the last phase, which was to begin in 1878-1886, marked the end of the division between the dead and the living, and the immediate reign of Sophia upon the non-incarnated souls (this probably meant the souls that are not incarnated in a body, or in other terms, that of the dead (La Sophia, p. 142). This characterization is understandable if we bear in mind the influence of spiritism on Solov’ev’s thought and his own spiritist practice in the 1870s. Interestingly, in automatic writing, Solov’ev wrote not only under the influence of Sophia, but also of his professor Pamfil Jurkevic, who had recently died (see PSS. 1, p. 181, n. p. 357). On Solov’ev’s automatic writing, see G.I. Culkov, M.V. Mikhailova (pref.). ‘Avtomaticeskie zapisi VI, Solov’eva’, Voprosy filosofii 1992, 8. Pp. 123-132. In the year 1877 and 1878, Solov’ev mainly wrote Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija and started giving his Lekeii o Bogocelovecestve.

70. April 1878 corresponded to the time he gave his Twelfth and last Lecture on the Humanity of God. On this period of Solov’ev’s life, see Nosov, 1992.

71. ‘Obscij smysl iskusstva’, p. 404.

72. Smysl ljubvi, p. 547.

73. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 253.

74. Ibid., p. 255.

75. Ibid. [first italics Solov’ev’s, second and third mine].

76. On the connected issue of prophetic ideal in the sophiological register of history, see paragraph Ac). Only in ‘Kratkaja povest’ ob Antikhriste’ did Solov’ev depict a negative outcome of history.

77. Another close connection between World Soul and future is made with respect to the word ‘nature.’ Solov’ev suggested that, etymologically speaking, the word itself means ‘which will be born’ and is in the future tense, which confirmed his point that the true subject of all-unity’ was still to be born (Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 134). The classical use of the term natura is of course a substantive.

78. The expression 'polovaja ljubov', literally 'sexual love', refers to love between the sexes, which includes sexual love, but also spiritual love between two persons. This enlightening comment is taken from: Vladimir Solovjov. Over liefde, Ton Jansen and Evert van der Zweerde (eds.) (Bergen op Zoom: Damon, 2001). p. 187.

79. La Sophia, p. 66.

80. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 296.

81. Solov'ev sought to posit radical equality between man and woman, radical individuality of both, while at the same time integrating his scheme in the traditional understanding of man's superiority over woman.

82. Kornhlatt 1991 has emphasized the androgynous character of Solov' ev' s ideal.

83. For a challenging interpretation of syzygy as discourse in Solov’ev’s Smysl ljubvi, see Edith Clowes, ‘The Limits of Discourse: Solov’ev’s Language of Syzygy and the Project of Thinking Total-Unity’, Slavic Review 55 (1996). 3. Pp. 552-566. Solov’ev did not elaborate on this term, but limited himself to stating that it was the only apt term that he had found to express his thought. About the use of the term by the Gnostics, see subsection 2b).

84. ‘Evrejstvo I khristianskij vopros’, p. 238.

85. See Kritika otvleeennykh nacal, p. 301: ‘Vdokhnovenic’: SS. 10, pp. 229-230.

86. On mysticism in Solov’ev, see Jonathan Sutton, The Religious Philosophy of Vladimir Solovyov, Towards a Reassessment (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1988): Martin George, Mystische und religiose Erfahrung im Denken Vladimir Solov’evs (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1988); Michael Aksionov Meerson, The Trinity of Love in Modern Russian Theology: The Love Paradigm and the Retrieval of Western Medieval Love, Mysticism in Modern Russian Trinitarian Thought (from Solovyov to Bulgakov). Series Studies in Franciscanism XX (Quincy, Illinois: Franciscan Press, 1988): Viktorija V. Kravcenko. Mistizm v. russkoj filosofskoj mysli XIX-nacala XX vekov (Moskva: Izdatcencentr, 1997), chap. 3: ‘VI. S. Solov’ev i gorizonty novoj metafiziki', pp. 69-155. On the basis of many or Solov'ev's publications, Kravcenko convincingly shows that mysticism interested Solov'ev throughout his career. Although she sometimes addresses pertinent questions, the argumentation often lacks coherence and rigour, as well as clear points. Besides, it does not lake into account the different periods of Solov’ev’s treatment of Sophia.

87. 'Mistika, misticizm’, SS 10. pp. 243-246: p. 244. By the term 'theosophy' he referred to the church fathers, and to Bohme's and Swedenborg's teaching, rather than to his own early definition of theosophy as a branch beside theocracy and theurgy. Nevertheless, this definition of theosophy applies to his activities as a philosopher, poet and mystic very well.

88. Kozyrev 1991, p. 165.

89. Khoruzij 2000. p. 75.

90. This remark has been made with respect to Bohme in Nicolas Berdiaeff -Etudes sur Jacob Bohme’, in the first French translation or Bohme's work: Jacob Bohme, Mysterium Magnum (Paris: Aubier, 1945). pp. 6-45: p. 7. It is perfectly applicable to Solov'ev as well.

91. See Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, p. 121.

92. Ibid., p. 111. transl. pp. 110-111.

93. ‘Poezija F.I. Tjutceva’ (1895), in: S. 1991. pp. 465-483: p. 472. Solov 'ev also expressed the dark force of nature in his poetry (see for instance ‘Sajma’, 'Imatra’, ‘Son najavu’, 'Kak v cistoj lazuri ...' (SS 12. pp. 41, 45, 45-6, 88-9). For an analysis of Tjutcev's influence on Solov’ev, see Florovsky. 'Tiutchev and Vladimir Soloviev', Collected Works 11. pp. 33-45.

94. 'Zemlja vladycica!...', (SS. 12. p. 22: Gazeli pustyn ....’ (Ibid., p. 90). Interestingly, the expression 'Eva or Turania' was used by the French writer and diplomat Melchior de Vogue (1848-1910) and applied to Sofija Khitrovo (S. Solovyov 2000, p. 243). This suggests that Solov'ev's poem was perhaps about simultaneously World Soul and his beloved Sofija Khitrovo.

95. Ex.: ‘Ili v javnom tainstve vnov' vizu socetanie / Zemnoj dusi so sveto, nezemnym' ('Zemija vladycica! ...’, p. 22).

96. For a sympathetic analysis of his poems on Sophia, see Sergei Bulgakov, 'Vladimir Solov' ev i Anna Smidt' in Tikhie dumy (1st publ. 1918: Moskva: Respublika, 1996), pp. 51-82.

97. Madey 1961, p. 39.

98. Although Solov’ev retained Comte’s notion of humanity as a metaphysical principle [see previous chapter, subsection 2c], he had strong objections to Comte’s identification of humanity as a principle of religion and as an object of cult: ‘Generally speaking, Comte was mistaken when he thought that the idea of a progressing humanity can replace the idea of an absolute being. The concept of progress or of perfectibility is logically conceivable only as a gradual assimilation by something imperfect of an objective perfection, which exists in its totality independently of the progressing subject and prior to it, for then every new step of increased perfection of this subject would be the production out of nothing, which is absurd – the less is in itself not a worthy basis for the more, and emptiness cannot be the only source of plenitude of being. Consequently, the true perfection of the “Great Being” cannot be humanity taken in isolation, but only the humanity of God.’ (‘Kont’, p. 406). For the same reason, the concept of World Soul necessitates a concept of God.

99. This point is convincingly demonstrated in Clowes 1996, p. 555.

100. ‘This idea [i.e. the union of contraries, MC] is but the expression of the great physical and moral reality of love’ (La Sophia, p. 92).

101. This teaching distinguished itself from other systems by its total structure (La Sophia, p. 106).

102. See La Sophia.

103. Smysl ljubvi, quoted in Clowes 1996, pp. 556-557 [italics Solov’ev’s].

104. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, p. 267.

105. See quote at the beginning of part 2 of this chapter [‘The Dialogue’]

106. For a masterful demonstration of this point, see Pamela Davidson, ‘Vladimir Solov’ev and the Ideal of Prophecy’, The Slavonic and East European Review 78 (2000), 4 pp. 643- 670; p. 647.

107. This aspect belongs to theology of history, and has therefore been examined in the corresponding section.

108. Solov’ev dealt with the topic of mysticism in numerous essays and polemic articles against such authors as Vvedenskij, Aksakov, Strakhov and Kavelin. Moreover, he displayed an immense knowledge of Eastern religious tradition, as shown in his first text on the mythological process and onwards. He also discussed the Western mystical tradition (e.g. Spinoza, Goethe). Finally, spiritism played a major role in Solov’ev’s life and work for many years. For a survey of these publications see Kraveenko 1997, pp. 69-155.

109. Unpublished letter to the Jesuit Perling, quoted in Stremooukhorf 1974, p. 144, n. II. This docs not mean, however, that the unconscious is prophetic by definition.

110. La Sophia (p. 330, italics mine) is a work that Davidson unfortunately did not include in her analysis. The Greek terms hypokeimenon and hypostasion literally mean 'object lying under the root' or 'put underneath' and refer to Solov'ev's total submission to Sophia. The synonymous term hypopodion was used in the Byzantine liturgy and known to Solov'ev (S. Solovyov 2000, p. 473).

111. ‘Mickevic', in: S. 1991. pp. 371-379: p. 376. On Mickiewicz see also the case study IV 'The Polish Question'.

112. This three-fold dimension of prophecy has been highlighted by Davidson 2000, p. 647.

113. 'Evrejstvo i khristianskij vopros', S. 1989 1, p. 231.

114. Definition from Ivan Aksakov, quoted in Philippot 1991, p. 10. For a discussion of the institution of the zemstvo. see case study V 'The Famine of 1891-1892'.

115. Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija, pp. 202-203. The name of this group, which we can hardly call an institution because of the lack of considerations on its organizational and institutional form in Solov'ev, varies in his work: people or simple people, educated society, and zemstvo in the Slavophile sense. The biographer Sergej Solov'ev also pointed to this connection with the Slavophiles (S. Solovyov 2000, p. 181).

116. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, pp. 266-267 [italics Solov’ev’s] See also paragraph 1c.

117. 'Tri sily', p. 207. The expression 'Eternal Testament' is a translation of Vecnyj zavet.

118. PSS. 2. p. 177 [italics mine].

119. Lemma 'Kabbalah', Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward Craig (ed.), 10 vols. (London et al.: Routledge. 1998). vol. 5. p. 171.

120. Ibid.

121. See 'Solov'ev i Kaballa', Issledovanija ob istorii russkoj mysli, Ezegodnik, 1998, pp. 7-104. Burmistrov shows that the biographical comments on Solov'ev's activities in London were made by people who ignored everything about the field of Kabbalah, and mixed it up with gnosis, Christian mystical writings and freemasonry. A close analysis of Sophia leads him to detect more Gnostic than Kabbalistic elements. For a study with a particular focus on sexuality in the Kabbalah and Solov'ev, see Kornblatt 1991.

122. Indeed, Solov'ev did not know Hebrew at that time, so it could only have been through translations.

123. We can also speak of an indirect influence of the Kabbalah on Solov'ev through Bohme, Swedenborg, Gichtel, Arnold, Pordage, Paracelsus, Agrippa, Saint-Martin, Martinez de Pasqually, Eliphas Levy, and Blavackaja (Burmistrov 1998, pp. 45-70).

124. These terms can be found mainly in La Sophia (ex.: pp. 56. 98. 164. 172). For a discussion of Solov'ev's treatment of Kabbalistic terminology, see Burmistrov 1998, pp. 30-39. The English transcription and translation of these terms are borrowed from the encyclopaedia article quoted above.

125. Burmistrov 1998. p. 95.

126. In this introductory essay, Solov'ev emphasised two characteristics of the Kabbalah that distinguished it from neo-Platonism, and which are interesting for our discussion: first the absence of dualism and of the idea of the fall in favour of a view of the world process in terms of the realisation of the (con)substantial [edinosuscee]: second. the central view of the human being as an absolute and all-embracing form of the universe as a whole' [Burmistrov] which led to 'a conscious and systematic anthropomorphism' (Solov'ev's words, quoted in Burmistrov 1998, p. 92; see also pp. 89-92).

127. ‘Kabbala', SS 10, pp. 339-343: p. 341.

128. See the quote containing the term Malchut, p. 137.

129. He mentioned the absence of boundaries between the different categories of the Kabbalistic cosmogonic hierarchy as well as between cosmogony (creation) and theosophy ('Kabbala'. p. 340).

130. The Sophia prayer was first published in Sergej Solov'ev's biography [S. Solovyov 2000 1. p. 125]. Sergej Solov'ev supposed that Solov'ev had written it under the inspiration of manuscripts that he was reading in the British Museum. Another hypothesis is that it was his own creation (see Sergej Bulgakov, 'Vladimir Solov'ev i Anna Smidt', op. cit., note by the editor, p. 442).

131. He intended to analyse gnosis and integrate the works recently published in the West. Aleksej Kozyrev sketched the context of Solov'ev's preoccupations with gnosis at that time, and mentioned this information found in the philosopher's correspondence (Kozyrev 1991, p. 153).

132. Aleksej Kozyrev, Gnosticeskie vlijanija v filosofii Vladimira Solov'eva (PhD thesis Moskva: Moskovskij gosudarstvennyj universitet, 1996); Maria Carlson, 'Gnostic elements in the Cosmogony of Vladimir Soloviev', in: Kornblatt and Gustavson 1996, pp. 49-67). In Kozyrev's and Carlson's enlightening analyses, I find support for my thesis that Sophia is primarily a link between the human and the divine. Carlson has however perhaps focused too much on the similarities between gnosis and Solov'ev's sophiology, as a result of which she tends to make Solov'ev a gnostic himself. Arguably. this is the purpose of her recontextualisation of his thought in a broader movement of modern gnosis including Blavackaja, Bulgakov, Blok, and Western anthroposophy. This raises the question of Solov'ev's exact role in the reactivation of Gnosticism in Russian culture. and to what extent the ground had already been laid for his contribution (spiritism, masonry, Bohme, Baader, etc.).

133. These points are taken from the entry 'Gnosticism', Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy 4. pp. 83-85.

134. The term pleroma is not a Gnostic invention but was already present in Plato's works.

135. 'Gnosticism', The Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy 3, pp. 336-342: p. 338.

136. 'Valentin i Valentiniany', 'Gnosticizm' (SS. 9. pp. 285-290, 323-328). He also wrote on another gnostic thinker, Basilides ['Vasilid'] (Ibid., pp. 290-2), in which, however, no sophiological themes are brought to the fore. In this analysis some topics have to be discarded for not being central in sophiology, such as the complex relationship Sophia- Christ-Logos.

137. In the same way. Solov'ev opposed the distant Gnostic God vs. the Christian God committed to the world. God and Jesus Christ vs. the Christian Godhuman, the aeons vs. Trinity, divided humanity vs. Christian united humanity, partial vs. total salvation, the end of history as merely a return vs. the end or history as spiritualised humanity or Kingdom of God ("Gnosticizm', pp. 325-326).

138. In her study on the influence of Gnosticism on Solov'ev's cosmogony, Maria Carlson has correctly recommended cautiousness in interpreting Solov'ev's entry on Gnosticism and noted the conformity of his views with the canon, that is, Irenaeus' Adversus omnes haereses. She also reminds that the church actively discouraged any research on a thinker's Gnosticism as further evidence that Gnosticism was an unwelcome subject (Carlson 1996, p. 53, 55). Worth mentioning is the fact that authors such as Goethe, Bohme, and even Hegel were acknowledged Gnostics.

139. 'Valentin i Valntiniany', p. 285.

140. Contesting the criticism made for instance by Zenkovsky of Solov'ev's incoherence in his sophiology, Carlson has made clear that the integration of two Sophias in Solov'ev's narrative was totally consistent within the Gnostic framework (p. 62).

141. ‘Valentin i Valentiniany', p. 286.

142. All these quotes arc taken from Ibid., pp, 286-288. Contrary to the entry "Gnosticizm', in this entry, Solov'ev uses the word pleroma with capitals [Pleroma]: for the sake of consistency, I write it 'pleroma'. Solov'ev correctly warned his readers that on the basis of Irenaeus's text, it was impossible to distinguish Valentinus' teaching from that of his successors. As a matter of fact, recent scholarship tends to identify strictly only one Sophia in Valentinus' thought (Gilles Quispel, 'The Original Doctrine of Valentinus the Gnostic'. in: Roelof van de Brock and Cis van Heertum (eds.). From Poimandres to Jacob Bohme: Gnosis. Hermetism and the Christian Tradition (Amsterdam: In de Pelikaan, 2000), pp. 233-263: pp. 246-249) or to distinguish between an old stage of Valentinism, which presents one Sophia (the 30th eon, higher Sophia), and a new stage, which presents two Sophias (with addition of Achamoth) (Christoph Markschies, Valentinus Gnosticus? Untersmchungen zur valentinianischen Gnosis mit einem Kommentar zu den Fragmenten Valentins (Tubingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1992), pp. 372- 373).

143. "Valentini Valentiniany', p. 288. The positive account of the category of process in the Gnostic teaching in this quote stands in sharp contrast with the critical stance adopted in 'Gnosticizm' concerning the same 'process". In 'Gnosticizm', which can be summarised as a Christian judgement of Gnosticism, Solov'ev denounced the Gnostic conception of process as a mere return without any gain for humanity, and as a process that applies only to one part of humanity ('Gnosticizm', p. 325).

144. For a comprehensive discussion or Solov'ev's use of Gnostic terms such as 'Demiurge', 'Satan', 'limit', as well as the reproduction of structural elements of the Gnostic myth (such as the interaction of centrifuge and centripetal principles), see Kozyrev 1996.

145. 'Valentin i Valentiniany', p. 288, italics Solov'ev's. The view or matter as an autonomous reality can be found indeed in the Presocratics, but not in Plato, as Solov'ev seems to suggest in the parenthesis.

146. From a more existential perspective on Solov'ev, Carlson interestingly interpreted Solov'ev's own life drama in the light of the Gnostic teaching: like the Gnostic mystic. Solov'ev took the risk of the descent into the abyss, the risk of being eternally trapped in matter, the risk of despair (p. 61).

147. Besides, the knowledge that the Gnostics possessed did not depend on their acts or belief, as Solov'ev himself pointed out ('Valentin i Valentiniany', p. 288).

148. Kozyrev 1996. p. 94.

149. See Smysl ljubvi, pp. 534-535; Quispel 2000, pp. 242-244.

150. Solov'ev specified that although he took the term syzygy from the Gnostics, his understanding of the term differed from theirs (Smysl ljubvi, p. 545).

151. Riemer Roukema, Gnosis and Faith in Early Christianity (London: SCM Press, 1999), p. 130.

152. Stremooukhoff 1974, 56 ff. This has been firmly established by Zdenck V. David, 'The influence of Jacob Boehme on the Russian religious thought'. Slavic Review, American Quarterly of Soviet and East European Studies 21 (1962). pp. 43-64. David devoted special attention to Solov'ev and emphasised his role as the thinker through whom 'Russian Boehmism was raised to a level where it could, and did, inspire serious and autonomous religious and philosophical thought' (p. 64). Apart from a thorough analysis of Bohme's influence on Solov'ev's sophiology, for which he employs extensive textual evidence, David provides us with an interesting history of the penetration of Bohmism in Russia.

153. Here he was decisively influenced by Pamfil Jurkevic, his philosophy professor and master at the University of Moscow, and by the philosopher and theologian Viktor Kudrjavcev-Platonov during his study at the Moscow Theological Academy. Imbued with the ideas of theosophic mysticism, Jurkevic counted Bohme and Swedenborg among the most important thinkers (David 1962, p. 59, referring to Solov'ev's commemorative article of Jurkevic).

154. Later on he wrote an entry for the Brokgauz-Efron encyclopaedia on Swedenborg, who was 'the most remarkable (after Jacob Bohme) theosophist of the modern times' ('Svedenborg', SS. 10, pp. 487-497). He also mentioned his own professor Pamfil Jurkevic as a member of a sect developed on the basis of the Swedish thinker's teachings called the Swedenborg church (Ibid., p. 497).

155. Two letters (1877, 1900) attest to Bohme's role: 'I have not found yet anything special in the library. There are in the mystics a lot of confirmations of my own ideas, but no new light, moreover nearly all of them have an exceptionally subjective character and, so to speak, drivelling [baveux]. I found three specialists on Sofija: Georg Gichtel, Gottfried Arnold and John Pordage. All three had a personal experience, nearly the same one as mine, and that is the most interesting, but properly in theosophy all three are rather weak, follow Bohme, but at a lower level than he did. I think that Sofija spent time on them more for [za] their innocence than for anything else. As a result, the real people remain all the same only Paracelsus, Bohme and Swedenborg, so that the field remains very wide for me.' (Pis'ma 2. p. 200, letter to the Countess Tolstoja, dated 27 April 1877). And in 1900 in a letter to Anna Nikolaevna Schmidt he wrote: 'Having read your letter with the greatest attention, I was glad to see how close you have come to truth in question of the greatest importance, which is contained in the essence itself of Christianity, but has not yet been posed clearly neither in the ecclesiastic, nor in the general philosophical awareness [soznanie], although isolated theosophers do talk about this aspect of Christianity (especially Jacob Bohme and his successors: Gichtel, Pordage, St-Martin. Baader). From 1877 onwards I had many times to touch upon this topic in public lectures, articles and books, observing the due caution. On the basis of many data, I think that a wide disclosing of this truth in the awareness and life of Christianity and whole mankind will come in the nearest future, and your apparition seems to me very important and significant' (Pis'ma 4, p. 8). Two other details, one at the start of Solov'ev's career, and one at the very end, point to the presence of Bohme in his thought. In Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija, Solov'ev strove to develop a 'theosophy', hereby showing a sense of affiliation with Bohme who had revitalised the term to designate his own work. And in Tri razgovora, he calls the alleged author of the' Povest' ob Antikhriste' Pansofij [Pansophius], a name which reminds one of Bohme's work 'Mysterium Pansophicum.

156. Most probably, Bohme or Bohmianism inspired Hegel on this point which became central to his work.

157. Alexandre Koyre, La philosophie de Jacob Boehme, 3rd ed. (Paris: Librairie philosophique J. Vrin, 1979), p. 344 [translation mine].

158. David has convincingly shown this point (p. 60).

159. Koyre 1979, p. 281. On this point. Bohme did not elaborate a conceptual apparatus as Hegel and Schelling would later do by relying heavily on Bohme's thought.

160. David 1962, p. 61.

161. David 1962, p. 61. In the formation of Sophia, however, the peculiar powers of the Trinity are not exerted on prime matter directly, but through the mediation of the Second Person, the Word, which for this purpose becomes three distinctive agents or Words. In as far as the Second Person actually carries out the entire creative action resulting in Sophia, the latter in its primary role as the Body of God is more specifically the body of the 'incarnate' Word, or the 'Body of Christ' (Ibid.).

162. See for instance pp. 248-250.

163. Koyre 1979, p. 212. It is unclear how Bohme connected the abovementioned notion of 'Eternal idea' with that of God's plan for the world. On the one hand. the 'Eternal idea' dictates the creation of Sophia, so cannot be equated to her. On the other hand, what is the 'Eternal idea', if not God's plan for creation as a whole?

164. David 1962, p. 62. n. 71. It is not clear whether Solov'ev borrowed the notion of light from him, which Bohme applied to Divine Sophia, in contrast with (worldly) darkness, or from other sources, such as the Bible, as Madey suggests (Madey 1961, p. 180). Concerning the principle of darkness, Solov'ev may have been more inspired by romanticism, directly or indirectly through Tjutcev [see also footnote 92 of this chapter].

165. Hereby I oppose David's treatment of Solov'ev's thought, which tends to identify this point as constant in Solov'ev's work.

166. David 1962, pp. 62-3.

167. La Russie et l’Eglise universelle, pp. 260-263.

168. Koyre 1979, p. 425, 431-2.

169. Interestingly, these are two points on which Solov'ev distinguished himself also from Hegel [see chap. III 'Philosophy of History in Solov'ev', subsection 2a], who probably picked up the second point from Bohme.

170. See for instance La Russie et l’Eglise universelle: Sophia incarnated herself in Mary and in Jesus Christ, but only in an individual aspect. Later she incarnated in a collective aspect in Church, The cult of Sophia as Church, is Russia's contribution to the world. Russia's message for the universal unification to come (p. 267). Bulgakov has also emphasised this point ('Vladimir Solov'ev i Anna Smidt', op. cit., p. 70).

171. Bulgakov has convincingly suggested that Bohme's Sophia was rather a ‘metaphysical principle', which actually concealed behind its androgynous character a true 'misogyny'. In contrast, for Solov'ev she vividly appeared in visions and was ornamented with all her feminine attributes and adulated precisely for them (Ibid., pp. 69-70).

172. That the German theosophist contributed to shaping this 19th century view cannot be contested. But two centuries separated the two men’s lives.

173. <Plany i cernoviki>, PSS. 2, p. 177 [italics mine].

174. <Cernovik o Sellinge>, PSS. 1. pp. 179-181. See commentary pp. 356-358. Some scholars have found support for their thesis of Schelling's influence in a manuscript recently published (1987). However, according to experts in Solov'ev archives, his document is probably not from Solov'ev's own hand (see commentary PSS. 1 p. 356). Further evidence for his admiration of Schelling is his statement that 'the teaching of Baader and the last "positive" philosophy of Schelling represent the attempts of a more real and concrete synthesis of the spiritual and physical elements in the world and in the human being' ('Priroda', p. 262 [italics mine]).

175. His religious philosophy and criticism of rationalism in particular had been enthusiastically received in Russia, often in combination with German romanticism, and reinterpreted by the Slavophiles. On the reception of Schelling in Russia, see A.V. Gulyga, Selling (Moskva: 1984). Among recent publications, see V.F. Pustarnikov (ed.), Filosofija Sellinga v Rossii (Sankt-Peterburg: Izd. Russkogo Khristianskogo gumanitarnogo instituta, 1998), p. 482, and D.K. Burlaka (ed.), Selling: Pro et contra (Sankt-Peterburg: Izd. Russkogo Khristianskogo gumanitarnogo instituta, 2001).

176. At his doctoral dissertation's defence, Solov'ev admitted a similarity of views with the late Schelling (i.e. his positive philosophy, not his philosophy of identity, which was pantheistic (Pis'ma 2, p. 100). Second, his article 'Idea and individuality in ancient paganism and Judaism' (which may have been a first version of the article on the mythological process written in 1873, and which Solov'ev first tried to publish in Russkij Vestnik) reminded Katkov of Schelling's lectures in Berlin ('Neskol'ko licnykh vospominanij o Katkove', S. 1989 2, p. 626).

177. These are the positions of Trubeckoj, Berdjaev, Mocul’skij, Stremooukhoff 1974, Muller, Copleston (mentioned in Madey 1961 pp. 97-109). This point has been made in S.B. Rocinskij, 'Filosofija tozdestva i metafizika vseedinstva: paralleli i sozvucija', in: Rocinskij 1999, pp. 86-97. A whole range of interpretations have been given as to the role of Schelling in Solov'ev's thought. Sestov concluded that Solov'ev took everything from Schelling, and lost himself in him: Muller, who rather focused on the issues of the essence of philosophy, theory of knowledge, and the problem of the fall, distinguished both. Szylkarski as well as Stremooukhoff pointed to the common sources of their thought (Bohme, the Kabbalah, Gnosticism), whereas Tilliette underlined the indirect influence of Schelling on Solov'ev via the Slavophiles (see M. Garcia Romero, 'Schelling's Reflection on Evil in the "Lectures on Godmanhood'", in: Borisova and Kozyrev 2001, pp. 220-241: pp. 221-222). Only Losev has categorically affirmed that Solov'ev came to views that were similar to Schelling's independently from him and that similarities were nothing but coincidences. Losev, who wrote his monograph on Solov'ev in the 1980s, did not know the manuscript of Sophia (first published in 1991) in which Solov'ev posed himself as Schelling's successor (Losev 2000, pp. 170-171). See also V.V. Lazarev, 'Filosofija VI. Solov'eva i Selling', in: Pustarnikov 1998, pp. 477-499. Unfortunately, Lazarev bases himself on the publication of a manuscript that is most probably not from Solov'ev's hand, which renders a good part of his analysis invalid.

178. Bulgakov is mentioned by Rocinskij 1999, pp. 89-90. See the highly valuable contribution of Paul Valliere, who aims at situating Schelling and Solov'ev in the history of modern religious thought (Valliere 2000b).

179. On this point, I agree with Groys (Groys 1995, p. 37). Schelling posed that the world [Weltamme] does not belong to divine nature, but cannot be excluded from it either. Also the commentators of Solov'ev's complete works have pointed out Schelling's role in the process of construction of Solov'ev's philosophical system (PSS 1, p. 357).

180. Rocinskij 1999, p. 90.

181. Ibid.

182. See entry 'Mirovaja dusa'. op.cit.

183. Dale E. Snow, Schelling and the End of Idealism (New York: State University of New York Press, 1996), pp. 85, 86.

184. Ibid., p.189.

185. Madey, p. 133.

186. F.W.J. Schelling, Philosophie der Offenbarung 1841/2 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1977), p, 185 [my translation].

187. 'Mifologiceskij process v drevnem jazycestve', p. 36. n. 38.

188. La Sophia, p. 116.

189. Rocinskij, the only scholar who has broached this question explicitly, has convincingly suggested that this distinguished Schelling's concept of World Soul from that of the Russians (Rocinskij 1999, p. 92).

190. According to Solov'ev, these views influenced Katkov ('Slavjanofil'stvo i ego vyrozdenie', p. 482. n. 1).

191. Sutton 1988. p. 76.

192. Schelling may have been influenced by Bohme on this point. On the role of Bohmian thought in Schelling's late works, see R.F. Brown, The Later Philosophy of Schelling: The Influence of Boehme on the Works of 1809-1815 (London & New York: Associated University Presses, 1977).

193. Cf. Snow 1996, p. 86; for Solov'ev, see the section 'The cosmic and historical process' in La Sophia, p. 116ff. Even though he affirmed the possibility of an alternative -- such as in the following statement: This 'pure and undetermined potency; has two possible ways: or to live. separated from God, or to identify herself with Divine Wisdom (La Russie et l'Eglise universelle, p. 254) -- his optimistic attitude tended to make him to see only the second way.

194. As Valliere has masterfully shown, Schelling had with his Potenzlehre brought to the fore a new way of conceptualising the reality of God: 'God has the power to posit something other than himself within his own being' (Valliere 2000b, pp. 121-122).

195. Ibid.

196. Although Solov'ev did not refer to Schelling on this point, commentators agree that he did borrow this definition from the German philosopher (See for ex. Stremooukhoff 1974, p. 68). The formulation of these aspects is taken from Valliere (Valliere 2000b, pp. 121- 122) and Stremooukhoff 1974, pp. 57-58.

197. Filosofskie nacala cel’nogo znanija, pp. 264-268. The same text is nearly exactly reproduced in Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, pp. 278-282 [quote from p. 282].

198. Kritika otvlecennykh nacal, p. 284.

199. Ibid., pp. 284-286.

200. Ibid., p. 282.

201. Valliere has convincingly shown that Solov'ev adopted the same scheme as Schelling in his philosophy of revelation, and adapted it to the history of religion, and especially to the three movements of the absolute (See Ctenija o Bogocelovecestve, which 'is clearly dependent on Philosophie der Offenbarung' (Valliere 2000b, p. 124), but also the 1873 article on the mythological process for a Schellingian influence (discussed by Stremooukhoff 1974, pp. 30, 85). Valliere notably points to the similarity between Schelling's ' living God' and Solov'ev's Bogocelovecestvo, especially with respect to the otherness of God within himself is His humanity. Copleston has also pointed to the Schellingian source of Solov'ev's 'second absolute' (reference given in Valliere 2000b, p. 125).

202. PSS. 2, p. 358, commentary on draft about Schelling.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 7:55 am

Synthesis

Throughout my study, I have disentangled the three registers that lie at the basis of Vladimir Solov'ev's conception of history, a synopsis of which is provided in the table below. It is relevant here to examine the results of his efforts to combine the three lines. Three modes of combination can be discerned, namely the complementation of two registers, tension, and synthesis between the three.

Firstly, there are points where two registers complement each other, illustrated by three examples. A clear example of the combination of theology of history and philosophy of history is the description of the historical becoming of Bogocelovecestvo in an evolutionistic scheme. Berdjaev soundly criticised this view as deterministic; indeed Solov'ev did not leave any room for chance and arbitrariness. [1] Secondly, Solov'ev posited theology of history as providing support for sophiology of history by defining Sophia in relation to the Trinity, in order to ground Sophia in the Christian tradition. This device also met with disapproval, this time from Orthodox commentators. [2] Finally, sophiology of history leans upon two core aspects developed by philosophy of history, namely the theory of process and the universal perspective.

Secondly, combining the three registers causes tension between them. For instance, Solov'ev's conception of time is ambivalent, torn between a theological understanding, according to which there is no proper time in nature but only mechanic repetition, and the philosophical and sophiological understanding on the other. The (philosophical) evolutionist understanding of natural time is made namely in terms of a positively valued process, while the freedom of nature as well as its potential of spiritualization is emphasised in sophiology of history. More importantly perhaps, his definition of time contains a contradiction with respect to the conception of God: from the theological perspective, God does not change, whereas from the sophiological perspective God is subjected to becoming.

Thirdly, the three registers can be combined in a fruitful synthesis. In one significant case, sophiology of history itself is this synthesis, offering a solution to the tensions between PH and TH regarding the conception of the meaning of history and Russia's place within it. We note a clash between the theological understanding that posits the meaning of things in God, and the philosophical one that posits it in the world. The only way to combine these two standpoints is to bring God closer to the world. One way to achieve this is to do so in a pantheistic system (God is all), which Solov'ev sought to avoid. The other way -- and here lies Solov'ev's originality -- is to make sophiology central, which posits Sophia as equivalent to ideal humanity. Accordingly, the national idea is in God (divine Sophia or Providence) and is realised in the process of humanity divinising itself (earthly Sophia or World Soul). This also allows us to see the action of Sophia at the national, mainly Russian, level, through the action of the prophet Solov'ev who directs his fellow countrymen towards the concrete realisation of Sophia on earth.

The synthetising function of sophiology of history can be best rendered in the following scheme:

Image

While theology of history lays emphasis on the relationship between the upper, divine level of transcendence, philosophy of history exclusively focuses on the events of the immanent world and draws a scheme of progressive development from the origin of human history toward the future. Sophiology of history combines and supersedes these two registers in several respects. It departs from (Solov'ev's) mystic experience, which allows to get an unmediated knowledge of the divine, to grasp history in its cosmic dimension from the beginning of the universe, and to include the lower level of matter and nature in the process toward fusion with God.

Another case of fruitful synthesis between the three registers is when sophiology of history is an element of this synthesis. As a matter of fact, the realisation of the ideal society in free theocracy is perhaps the field in which Soiov'ev most elaborated his synthesis of the three registers. [3] Working at the concept of the ideal society, he reflected especially on the relationship between the church and the state. This led him to reject both the assimilation of church into state, which had been adopted under the cesaro-papist Byzantine rule, and the strict separation between church and state as practised in Western Europe. The solution that he introduced was that of a harmonious collaboration of the church, the state and educated society (also called the people, or zemstvo). In this respect, his project of free theocracy was the most developed of these attempts at a synthesis. Solov'ev normatively described the role of the chief groups, and their leaders, the pope, king, and prophet, in respectively the theological, philosophical, and sophiological registers of history. In this respect, the three registers find support in Solov'ev's theocratic view on human agency in history.

In the second part of my research, I explore to what extent and in which ways Solov'ev addressed the church, state, and educated society in order to foster the implementation of his ideal of free theocracy on Russian soil.

Image
_______________

Notes:

1. Berdjaev in Russkaja ideja, referred to by Ignatow 1997, p. 14.

2. Florovsky: Solov'ev 'somehow literally left the Church' (Georges Florovsky, Ways o/Russian Theology II, Collected Works 6, p. 245.

3. The synthesis between theology of history and philosophy of history is visible in his general concept of 'Christian politics’.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 7:55 am

Part Two: Case Studies

Introduction

Objective


In this part of my research, I conduct a historical analysis of Solov'ev's interventions in five widely debated issues in his time, namely the Polish, Jewish, and Old Believers questions, the tsaricide in 1881, and the famine of 1891-1892. This analysis hereby covers all concrete issues and debates to which Solov'ev committed himself in the Russian context. [1] On the one hand, this historical approach aims at placing the publicist's texts in the context in which they were written, published, and reacted to, and addresses the following questions: the knowledge of the issue displayed by him, his position within the ongoing debates, his addressees, and the perception of his interventions by his fellow countrymen. On the other hand, from a perspective internal to his work, I apply the results of Part One in an analysis of the three registers of history as they manifest themselves in these interventions.

In these five case studies, I shed light on Solov'ev's efforts to create the conditions for Russia's development as a Christian nation, as a first step towards the practical incarnation of Sophia in free theocracy. He believed that the implementation of free theocracy should, initially, take place in Russia. Significantly, all his interventions address issues related to the development in Russia of the third pillar of his theocracy, namely society. Solov'ev untiringly exhorted his fellow countrymen to develop that what today some would call a 'civil society', and in his own terms, a harmonious, organic or integral society. [2] Not only did he exhort educated society to gather around a (Christian) unifying principle, but he also called for more solidarity between educated society and the peasantry for the building of society as a whole. [3] This permanent factor shows to what extent this ideal whole, which forms the core of his social commitment as a prophet, departed from his concrete perception of late tsarist society. In this sense, the case studies bring to the fore an image of Solov'ev as a man of his time, whose thought, however idealistic it may sometimes appear to the reader, was nurtured by the observation of social groups. The lack of cohesion, in particular between its urban and country components as well as between the religious communities, prompted him to fiercely react.

Having his ideal of a Russian society in mind, Solov'ev intervened on certain issues in a characteristic manner, in which we can discern some tensions. These show how challenging his mission was as prophet, namely to translate a higher truth into the concrete situation of Russia. The tensions concern his approach to the issue, his position with respect to religious minorities, and his treatment of history.

First, his approach is a primarily religious and moral, Russo-centric and future-oriented perspective, and is only in exceptional instances factual and directly practical. Challenging in this respect is the definition that Solov'ev gave of himself: 'as a publicist, for whom it is not that, out of which certain phenomena form themselves and how they occur, but that to which they lead (cui bono?), it was necessary for me to emphasise the practical result.' [4] The five cases offer a wide scale of positions between a practical approach and a speculative interpretation, with each case showing a different balance between the two.

In the second place, a tension can be discerned in his treatment of religious minorities, which forms the core of three of the five case studies, namely the Old Believers, the Jews, and the Catholic Poles. Solov'ev had an ambivalent relationship to these religious minorities, which on the one hand consists of respect, but on the other hand demonstrates no real understanding of their position.

Finally, his treatment of history is characterised by a tension between his belief in progress and his universalism (PH), and his 'Christiano-centrism' (TH), reinforced by the conviction that progress can only consist in sophianic development (SH). I will show how for each issue his original combination of the three registers of history caused a misunderstanding on the part of his fellow countrymen.

Method-related considerations

Within the framework of my research focused on Solov'ev, I have limited my historical investigation of Russian public opinion to a highly restricted field, namely the same genre, place and period of publications as Solov'ev (publicislika in St. Petersburg and Moscow journals 1880-1900). [5] I have classified the publications according to their political adherence and sketched general tendencies with respect to each issue. For this purpose I base myself on the following, inevitably reductive, but commonly accepted classification of Russian public opinion into conservatives (monarchists ranging from the Slavophiles to clerical and nationalist conservatives) and progressives (liberals, legal and revolutionary populists, and socialists).

I try to assess Solov'ev's interventions by confronting his statements on the debated issues with those of his fellow countrymen. Considering his statements on history within his texts as 'intersubjectively understandable and verifiable', I also address them on the basis of three modes of verification: pertinent sources and actual state of research; optimal integration of all available historical data; and rigorous, consistent and non-contradictory explicit and implicit models of explanation. [6] The two former criteria are especially relevant for assessing the arguments of a historian. But are these criteria, which were indeed initially defined in order to be applied to historical research, also relevant when applied to a philosopher's writings on history? I can only try to give a cautious answer on this point. Of course, Solov'ev was not an expert, for instance, on the facts of the Polish question in the way a historian was or is. But the fact that he claimed to know the essence of the Polish question allows us to take this claim seriously and examine on what arguments he bases his conclusions. Therefore, the third criterion in particular is applied, while the former two are applied more generally.

In order to address the abovementioned questions, I have structured the case studies as follows:

1. Introduction

a) Presentation of the issue and state of the question
b) Historical sketch of the issue
c) Debates on the issue: main tendencies

2. Solov'ev's intervention

a) Overview of his publications and undertakings
b) His perception of the issue
c) Confrontation of his view with those of the Russian public (debates)
d) Theology of history, philosophy of history and sophiology of history in his publications

3. Conclusion

_______________

Notes:

1. My objective is to unravel how Solov'ev positioned himself within existing social debates. To issues like the 'Eastern question', namely the relationships with Turkey, Solov'ev only devoted a few passages. He also dealt with nationalism and church reunion, but these issues fall beyond the scope of this research for the following reasons. His treatment of nationalism mostly remained theoretical, and when it touched upon concrete issues, these are the religious minorities analysed in my case studies. As far as the debate about church reunion is concerned, it is religious rather than social; besides, it did not exist until Solov'ev himself un lashed it.

2. For an analysis of Solov'ev's position in the light of 20th-century discussions on civil society, see Machiel Karskens, 'Free Theocracy and Civil Society: Some Reflections on Solov'ev's Justification of the Good', in: van den Bercken et al. 2000, pp. 447-460.

3. These two motives appear quite clearly in a text written in 1884. 'Evrejstvo i khristianskij vopros' (S. 1989 1. pp. 206-256: p. 246).

4. 'Zamecanija na lekciju P.N. Miljukova' (S. 1989 2. pp. 492-496: p. 494 [italics mine]).

5. I hereby leave two main problems to the cultural historians. Firstly, the problem of a sociology of reading in pre-revolutionary Russia, shedding light on the question of the modes of encounter between the world of the text (newspaper, government report or statute) and that of the reader. The second, related issue is that of a history of representations in pre-revolutionary Russia. The multiple sets of cultural points or reference, values, and beliefs, according to one's social group, place, political conviction etc., contributed to shape one's representation of such issues as the famine of 1891-1892.

6. These criteria come from Wolfgang J. Mommsen, 'Social Conditions and Social relevance in Historical Judgments', History and Theory: Studies in the Philosophy of History 17 (1978), 4, pp. 19-35: p. 33.
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

Re: History, Sophia and the Russian Nation: A Reassessment o

Postby admin » Thu May 10, 2018 7:57 am

I. The Tsaricide of March 1st, 1881

There is a great moment of self-condemnation -- or self-justification: let Russia's tsar and autocrat manifest in deed that he is foremost a Christian [ ... ] [1]


1. Introduction

On March 1st, 1881, Tsar Alexander II was assassinated in St. Petersburg by members of the revolutionary movement Narodnaja Volja [the Will of the People], sending a profound shockwave throughout Russia. Solov'ev publicly expressed his views on the event on two occasions. He rejected the acts of the revolutionary movement but all the same appealed to the tsar to forgive his father's murderers. The latter message provoked a stir among the public and fierce disapprobation from the authorities. Solov'ev was accused of taking the side of the revolutionaries. This case tells the story of a courageous intervention and a painful misunderstanding between Solov'ev and his contemporaries.

March 1st 1881 is generally considered a turning point in the tsarist regime towards the period of counter-reforms until the Revolution of 1917. [2] The role of Narodnaja Volja in undermining autocracy in particular has been the object of numerous studies. [3] Significantly, most historical works that deal with March 1st mention Solov'ev as the most prominent voice on the issue of the murder, and have documented his intervention through the publication of various related archive material. [4] All biographical works on Solov'ev deal with this dramatic episode in his life, although no proper historical study has yet been performed of Solov'ev's intervention. [5]

a) Thesis

With respect to this case I would like to defend the following points. Firstly, this unique occasion when Solov'ev publicly admonished the tsar had a religious rather than political tenor. Secondly, there was a tension, which partly explains the misunderstanding of his message, between his highly speculative interpretation of the events and his acute sense of crisis in Russian society. Thirdly, his opinion was mostly in line with ongoing debates, especially with the conservative camp. Fourthly, his three-fold conception of history proved decisive to the extent that he found there the theoretical framework, the practical motivation to intervene and the justification of his own position as prophetic leader of society and of the people, and advisor of the tsar. In order to make this assessment, his lectures are set against the background of political developments in 1880-1881 (1b) and of the debates in the press after the murder (1c). After a short account of this two-fold context, I present in (2a) Solov'ev's texts and reaction of the authorities, in (2b) confront his views with the political context and (2c) the debates, and in (2d) bring to the fore the decisive role of his conception of history as a practical and theoretical source of inspiration to intervene (2d).

b) The historical context: Policies and terrorism 1878-1881

The second half of the reign of Alexander II was in many respects a return to the era preceding the reforms of the 1850-1860s. As part of this reactionary mood, the government attempted to crush the radicalising populist movement with widespread trials. After unsuccessfully trying to provoke an uprising among the peasants to overthrow the government, the populists turned to terrorism. From 1878 onwards several conspiracies, terrorist acts and attempts at murder aimed to destroy key figures of the centralised power, namely the police, high officials, and even the tsar. The radical wing Narodnaja Volja was created in 1879. Its executive committee, although only about thirty-strong, devoted its full energy to a terrorist offensive against the government and resolutely voted for the death of Alexander 11. [6] When they finally succeeded, instead of the chaos and anarchy that they had expected, repression swept over the capital. After a short trial on March 30th, the four main organisers of the murder were condemned and hanged. The populist movement was crushed.

Facing strikes, growing protest among students, a lack of support from the educated class and a severe explosion at the Winter Palace, the tsar decided to adopt a more moderate policy that would partly meet the demands of public opinion. [7] He appointed Mikhail Loris-Melikov as head of an administrative commission that would examine participation of representatives of the population in the government. In 1880-1881, Loris-Melikov, meanwhile appointed Minister of the Interior, initiated a 'dictatorship of the heart.' Under his leadership the commission discussed the project of reforms that would be a first step towards cooperation between representatives of the nation and the government. On March 1st, Alexander II officially approved of this project, but was killed that very day.

Alexander II's sudden death raised the question of the direction the new regime should take. Aware of the highly uncertain climate since the murder, and for fear of revolutionary uprisings, Alexander III, son and successor of the assassinated tsar, did not hesitate long. [8] It took him and his right hand Pobedonoscev only two months after his accession to the throne to officially announce a definitive turn towards a reactionary regime with his 'Manifesto of the inviolability of autocracy.' In doing so, the idea of reforms towards a constitution was eliminated from the political agenda. All ministers, Loris-Melikov included, were replaced by conservative politicians who were devoted to reinforcing absolute monarchy.

c) The debates

In the capital, the terrorist act was met with a mixture of stupor, anguish and dumb waiting. [9] The first reaction was a unanimous consensus to condemn the murder of the tsar- liberator and to advocate the necessity of eradicating terrorism. After the initial shock, divergent views crystallised. However, the press was soon restricted in its freedom. Three days after the murder, the organ of censorship instructed by Loris-Melikov threatened to close those press organs that published anything about the future plans of the government, especially on the project of a so-called 'constitution'. [10] In this very tense climate, the two main camps that had struggled over the past years, the liberals and the conservatives, still held opposite views. Each referring to the need for a 'unification of the tsar with the people', both camps substantiated this claim with different content. This is examined below, as is the official reaction of the populist Narodnaja Volja with respect to the two main issues that divided public opinion, namely the origin of the sedition [kramola], and the orientation of the new regime. [11]

Through their newspapers and journals, the liberals interpreted the sedition as the outcome of the reactionary turn in Alexander II's reign. [12] The reforms initiated in the 1860s had aimed at raising national consciousness and inviting social forces to participate and collaborate with political forces in new institutions. These had not been created however, and instead public opinion was repressed. What was to be done now? The liberals answered unanimously by indicating the necessity of pursuing the reforms initiated by Loris-Melikov. Without using the prohibited term 'constitution' they made clear that restricting autocracy was the only solution, and alluded to the project of restoring the representative institution of the zemskij sobor. [13] In this way they promoted a unification of the tsar and the people through representative organs.

The conservatives, including the Slavophiles who had inspired Alexander II's reactionary policy, held the opposite opinion. [14] Sedition had appeared in Russia because of the liberalism that was guilty of corrupting Russian society. The revolutionary movement was alien to Russian life. The Slavophile Ivan Aksakov went further back to Peter the Great as having first introduced Western principles in Russian life, and provoking the subsequent gap between the tsar and the people. [15] The only way to suppress this gap was to defend the inviolability of autocracy, which was 'the symbol of the unity of the state and the people.' [16] Aksakov enthusiastically welcomed Alexander Ill's 'Manifesto' as a return of order. [17] However, he defended at the same time the idea of representation of the people in government and tried to influence the government to restore the zemskij sobor. [18] On this point, the liberals and the Slavophiles agreed. But within the conservative camp, the authoritarian Pobedonoscev swept away his proposal, and any discussion on representative power was eliminated.

Shortly after the assassination, Narodnaja Volja made its claims clear in a public document distributed widely throughout the capital, the 'Letter of the "executive committee" to the tsar', written by Lev Tikhomirov and Nikolaj Mikhajlovskij. [19] In this document they ascribed the origin of the movement to the growing 'discontent of the people and Russia's strife to new social forms.' [20] They uncompromisingly demanded the abolition of absolute monarchy and the 'voluntary transmission of the supreme power to the people' through a national assembly of elected representatives. If not, the revolutionary organisation would spread across the entire empire and in a bloodbath destroy the old order. [21] Their claims were of course dismissed and the police actively repressed the whole movement, including the moderate wing known as Cernyj Peredel [Black Repartition], which promoted a gradual transition towards an equal repartition of all land among the peasants. [22]

2. Solov'ev's intervention

a) Solov'ev's speeches and the reaction of the authorities

i) Speeches


Solov'ev did not express himself in the press, but gave his interpretation of the events orally. This can hardly be considered a tactical move as he did not try to avoid provocation. He expressed himself in two lectures. [23] The first was part of his programme of academic courses on the history of Ancient philosophy at the Higher Women Courses program, and can be considered Solov'ev's immediate reaction to the tsar's murder in a semi-public sphere. [24] Given less than a fortnight after the murder on March 13th, it was eloquently entitled 'The meaning of the present events'. Instead of the planned lecture on Ancient philosophy, the philosopher chose to present his interpretation of the murder, which he saw as the result of the universal historical process. In his talk, he drew a line that had started from the appearance of Christianity and had been diverted in the Middle Ages by the growing role of rationality in Catholic theology. From there on, pure rationality combined with fanaticism such as in the Inquisition, through the French Revolution, had led to the contemporary revolutionary movement in Russia. Through this genealogy, Solov'ev yielded a moral condemnation of the revolutionary movement.

His second lecture, held two weeks later, contained a far more subversive message. It was held in public by the young philosopher in front of about eight hundred people at the Society of Credit on March 28th, the very day that the judgement had to be passed on the regicides. [25] Although part of a series of three lectures on the history of enlightenment in Russia, Solov'ev obviously again gave a spontaneous speech. [26] In the same vein as in his first lecture, Solov'ev first rejected the populist worldview, this time by opposing to it the faith of the simple people [narod]. This faith included faith in the government as a means of realising the ideal Christian society on earth. Solov'ev then examined the Christian tenor of the function of tsar. He urged Alexander III to forgive the murderers of his father, Alexander II, or else people would 'detach' themselves from the state power. [27] His message was two-fold: he condemned the terrorist acts and he recommended the abolition of the death penalty. Asked about his opinion on the trial, he answered that according to Christian principles the death penalty was unforgivable and should be abolished. [28] That was enough for a part of the audience to interpret these words and the lecture as a defence of the murderers. The audience enthusiastically applauded and gave him a loud ovation. [29]

Facing this huge misunderstanding and the threat of consequent official measures, Solov'ev wrote a letter to tsar Alexander III to present his views and correct the rumours. [30] He assured him that his speech had been motivated only by his faith in the spiritual force of Jesus Christ, in the Russian people, and in the tsar as the 'representative' of the spirit of the people. His admonishment was only intended to urge the tsar to achieve a great moral deed.

ii) The official reprisals

Solov'ev's public intervention and the stir it provoked did not remain unnoticed by the authorities, which called him to order. Three official documents describe Solov'ev's interaction with the authorities. [31] Firstly, a report was written to Loris-Melikov by city governor Baranov. Baranov had been appointed after the tsaricide to fight sedition and was known for being 'unintelligent' and a 'bully', good at 'heightening fear and confusion in governmental circles about newly-uncovered plots.' [32] He reported that Solov'ev had 'jutted out into [vdalsja] very inappropriate arguments concerning the significance and meaning of the death penalty', and found Solov'ev's act 'sad, since by his tactlessness he [Solov'ev] had provoked demonstrations, though unimportant ones, on the part of some attendees.' [33] Secondly, Solov'ev, summoned by Baranov, wrote an official document in which he assured that the public included 'many famous and estimated figures who, as I know, rightly understood the meaning of my speech and can confirm my testimony.' [34] This document, as well as his letter to the tsar, demonstrated Solov'ev's sincerity. In addition, a number of high-ranked figures appear to have interceded in his favour so that Solov'ev avoided harsh punishment. [35] In the third official document, a report advising the tsar concerning his decision about Solov'ev, Loris-Melikov pointed out that Solov'ev actually deserved 'not only to be deprived of his title of professor and forbidden to give public lectures, but also to be expulsed from St. Petersburg. [36] He did however add that there were extenuating circumstances. Given the fact that he was the son of the famous and recently deceased historian, and given his ascetic way of life and convictions, a 'strict reprimand [vnusenie]' would suffice. [37] The tsar eventually decided to communicate this reprimand through the intermediary of the Minister of Education and forbade Solov'ev to give public lectures. [38] This ban lasted for a couple of months. Solov'ev was in a nervous state of mind throughout spring. In the course of the year, he retired from university lecturing, and later from the scientific committee of the Ministry of Education, with which he was associated. [39]

b) Confrontation with historical context of government policies and terrorism

Solov'ev's intervention took place between the tsaricide and Alexander III's 'Manifesto', that is, precisely in the period of transient uncertainty about the future regime. He sensed that this was a critical moment when Russia stood at a crossway. In his public lecture, he mentioned the danger of the population rejecting the tsar, hereby alluding to the threat of an uprising or even a revolution. Still, his formulation was unclear: he threatened 'we will detach ourselves from it [the state power)'; this 'we' most probably referred to educated society, of which he was a member and which was his audience, rather than to the simple folk. [40] Anyway, by asking the tsar not to condemn the murderers, and by making the duty of the tsar depend on the ideals of the people, he was, consciously or not, taking the risk of being associated with the revolutionaries. This was for the tsar 'a great moment of self-condemnation -- or self-justification', he claimed. [41] In those agitated days, this may have sounded particularly provocative to those officials who were on the lookout for any statement that placed absolute monarchy in doubt.

Solov'ev, however, did not view the contribution of the people from a political or institutional perspective. No allusion was made to Loris-Melikov's attempts at creating institutions that represented the people in government. Similarly, Solov'ev discussed neither the potential reduction of the tsar's power nor a liberal vs. reactionary orientation of the future regime. Instead, he focused exclusively on that single moment: the tsar's power to modify the verdict on the murderers. In his eyes this was the critical choice that would orient the future of Russia. Whether he intended it or not, he conveyed the idea that the attitude of the population -- either respect for and thus the maintenance of autocracy, or rejection of and thus revolution -- would depend on the tsar's attitude towards the murderers.

In contrast, Solov'ev's valuation of the revolutionary movement was less speculative, as is shown by two statements. Firstly, he explicitly condemned the use of terrorism for realising a better society. Secondly, he effectively pointed out the affiliation of the Russian revolutionary movement with the French Revolution. The Jacobine approach was after all the core of Petr Tkaeev and Sergej Necaev's ideology. [42]

To summarise, Solov'ev's interpretation did not address the current political preoccupations of the government. By discussing the idea of the tsar and the intellectual affiliation of the populists, he rather reflected from the standpoint of ideas. As to the contribution of the people, he only emphasised its moral role and relationship with the tsar. Nevertheless, the tension between a speculative interpretation of the events and the feeling that Russia stood at a critical point in time, ensured that his call to the tsar suggested a questioning of absolute monarchy. This therefore entailed a subversive political message, which was actually a reaction to a deep political crisis.

c) Confrontation with debates

Solov'ev was not the only one to react to these events, but his second lecture was considered exceptionally bold and caused a stir in St. Petersburg's intellectual and governmental circles. [43] The intensity of the reaction was proportional to the misunderstanding of the reception of the lecture. Both the audience and the authorities understood his call to the tsar as a justification of the murder of Alexander II, which led to adulation by some, and the severest condemnation by others. [44]

Solov'ev followed the general tendency set in the debates in two main respects. Firstly, he wanted to address the root of the revolutionary movement. Secondly, the motive advocated by both the liberals and the conservatives of unification between the tsar and the people was also central in his own speeches.

i) The liberals

Compared with the interpretations given in liberal circles, his treatment of the issue differs by showing absolutely no interest in discussing the concrete modalities of the future political regime and the continuation or not of the reforms initiated by Loris-Melikov towards popular representation in the government. A comment by a liberal who had attended the lecture is revealing: 'He pictured such a highly idealised [takoj ideal 'no- vysoklj] image of the tsar that could not exist in reality.' [45] Whether this judgement also applies to Solov'ev call to abolish death penalty remains unclear. In any case, his tone was not that of a scholar appealing for a rational approach to the phenomenon and envisaging practical solutions to a political crisis.

ii) The conservatives

With some conservatives he shared not only a preaching tone, but also a number of principles. Faith in absolute monarchy appears in his message quite clearly. The fact that he ascribed the source of the revolutionary movement to French revolutionaries, and further back, to the Inquisition, perfectly matched the conservative Slavophile thesis that the revolutionary movement was alien to Russia. However, the conservatives reacted to his lecture with great disapproval. The authorities considered it highly provocative and that it exposed 'highly displaced opinions' on the verdict of the tsar's murderers. [46] Slavophile Ivan Aksakov also reacted furiously to the fact that Solov'ev had mentioned his lecture and that Solov'ev had associated himself with him in public. [47]

iii) The populists

The actual main targets of Solov'ev's two lectures were the populists. He pinned down the foremost intellectual weakness of populism as a whole by attacking 'the present-day revolutionary movement' and 'personal enlightenment.' [48] He was most probably aware of the demands of Narodnaja Volja's made public in their 'Letter of the "executive committee" to the tsar'. By condemning this particular terrorist act and associating it with the French Revolution, he made it clear that he totally disapproved of their projects, as well as any revolution. However, it is in some respect revealing that Solov'ev was associated by part of the audience and the authorities with the movement that he condemned with all his might. This misunderstanding suggests that he shared more with them than he himself was ready to admit. Firstly, he operated in a similar manner, by speaking publicly and directly to the tsar. Secondly, the vehemence with which he took it upon himself to speak in the name of the narod conveys a sense of competition between himself and the populists as to who would have the last word on the true 'will of the people'. This point is related to his views on history and is therefore examined in the next paragraph.

To summarise, his intervention was to a large extent typical of the debates held after March 1st. He broached the same issues, namely the origin of the terrorist act and the future of the country. More specifically, his attachment to autocracy and his condemnation of the revolutionary movement as the product of an alien influence placed him alongside the conservatives. However, his stance was unique in two respects. The appeal to the tsar not to apply death penalty was a first. [49]

Lev Tolstoj had approached the tsar with the same request, but did not do so publicly. [50] Moreover, through his threatening tone Solov'ev's appeal surpassed Tolstoj's supplication in boldness. Secondly, the threat that the population, whether educated society or the people, would divert from the tsar was highly subversive. How could he have the courage, temerity or naivety to express himself so provokingly? His conception of history played a significant role in shaping his theoretical stance as well as his position with respect to the protagonists, namely the tsar, educated society and the people.

d) Theology of history, philosophy of history and sophiology of history

Solov'ev's argumentation rests for a good part on historical considerations, which can be analysed with the help of the three registers that I have discerned.

The theological perspective on history is predominant and provides the framework for Solov'ev's moral interpretation of March 1st. He identified two reference points, namely the first manifestation of absolute truth in the person of Jesus Christ, characteristically labelled as the decisive 'fact' of history, and the absolute truth as ideal to be realised in next future. However, next to this positive line, he also drew a negative one. Within the Christian world, a process had developed that was based on the same strife for realising truth, but by means of pure rationality and violence. [51] At some point, men lost the meaning of truth and the divine principle, and renounced God. What was left was only reason and instinct, that is, human and animal principles. History is read from the point of view of the axiological opposition between (positively charged) Christian ethics and (negatively charged) rationality and violence. In a somewhat Slavophile stance, Solov'ev interpreted March 1st as the exponent of a depravation of Christianity that had its roots in the Catholic institution of the Inquisition: 'These fanatical zealots of the letter of the law, who wanted to establish truth by violence and murder, should be considered the ancestors of contemporary revolutionaries.' [52]

The positive line was not lost, however. Solov'ev advocated that it be picked up and demonstrated that Christian values were preserved in the faith of the Russian people. [53] In this way, he defined the essence of the people within a theological framework of history, with a blend of sophiological motives, as we shall see. His appeal to the tsar not to apply the death penalty is the direct result of his theological perspective on history. If the tsar wanted to act as a truly Christian tsar, he had to apply Jesus Christ's law of general pardon [vseproscenie]. Only in this way would he ground his reign on the Christian tradition.

In contrast, the philosophical perspective on history is underdeveloped. Only Solov'ev's acknowledgment of the state as a means for realising the good belongs to this register. [54] His statement that the simple people accepted the state was probably aimed at the populists, who also spoke in the name of the people and promoted the overthrowing of the present state. However, he qualified this statement. He insisted that the state did not have an independent status, but was merely 'a means subordinated to the realization of the ideal', the last being dictated by the faith of the people. [55] This strongly suggests a rejection of the Hegelian and liberal conception of the state as the supreme vehicle of progress. Another classic category of philosophy of history, namely that of 'narod', seems here to be defined by uncommon factors. In the philosophical register of history, narod commonly means nation or the people. In his speeches, Solov'ev referred to it rather as 'the simple folk' and filled this category with theological motives, as we have seen, defining narod as the bearer of Jesus Christ's absolute truth.

More fundamentally, however, he invested the notion of simple folk with sophiological motives. He argued that in opposition to the revolutionary movement, the simple people believes that the human world and nature have 'one soul, and that this soul strives to incarnate the divine principle, to generate the Divinity within itself [... ]. It is the world soul, primal matter, the mother of all what exists.' [56] His main point was that it was the simple folk, not the populists, who really understood the underlying process going on in history with their spiritual sense of nature and the world. This process was not limited to the realisation of a material or un-religious ideal, such as that of the populists, but implied a spiritual evolution involving nature and the human being.

By putting his own sophianic convictions in the mouth of the people, Solov'ev made himself their spokesman. [57] His prophetic stance extended to educated society, which was the main addressee of his speeches and the group to which he belonged: 'We (educated society), have to say [... ]', he wrote in his declaration to the city governor. [58] But more explicit perhaps are the concluding words of his provocative speech: 'Let the people recognise their soul in our thought and their voice in our advice; and then they will hear us, understand us, and follow us.' [59] The sense of emergency resounds clearly from his speech and points to the role that he took upon himself. [60] He acted as a moral leader of educated society and of the simple people, and as an advisor to the tsar, whom Solov'ev was not afraid to address as an equal. This prefigured the role that he later ascribed to the prophet within his theocratic ideal.

3. Conclusion

Solov'ev's courageous intervention after March 1st shows a unique moment when he publicly addressed the tsar. He expressed himself without tactically taking into account the tension in the capital in the weeks following the murder of Alexander II. Feeling that Russia faced a critical choice, he argued that this choice depended on the tsar's decision to apply or not apply the death penalty, hereby elevating the debate to a highly speculative and religious level, in which Realpolitik was irrelevant. Accordingly, it was his faith in the monarchic principle that prompted him to express his expectations with powerful threatening words, which in their turn provoked the misunderstanding of his message. Apart from his admonishing the tsar, his views were quite in line with the monarchist and Slavophile stance of the conservatives. This discrepancy shows that despite ideological affinities, Solov'ev acted as an independent intellectual. His three-fold conception of history provided the framework that allowed him to condemn the revolutionary movement, to speak in the name of the simple folk, to stand as the leader of educated society, and to address the tsar as an equal.

In this first significant and perhaps most resounding intervention in Solov'ev's entire life, all the ingredients are already present for his future social commitment, namely firstly history as an essential component of the discourse; secondly the public position he occupied as a prophet; thirdly his addressee, educated society; and fourthly a skirmish with the authorities. From that moment onwards, Solov'ev suffered relentless hindrance and control from the organs of censorship, particularly from the high procurator of the Holy Synod Pobedonoscev, for the rest of his life.

Alexander III did not counter the court's verdict regarding the criminals. This may be Solov'ev's first disillusionment as regards Russia's ability to move on along the path of moral improvement. Not accidentally, in the following years, Solov'ev devoted his energy to mobilising the very group that he felt could sustain the monarch to rule according to Christian principles, namely educated society. The institutional embedding of the action of educated society remained beyond his concern, as his speeches after March 1st already showed.

_______________

Notes:

1. 'Publicnaja lekcija' (S. 1989 I, p. 42). This chapter is an extended and revised version of an earlier publication: Manon de Courten, 'The Prophet Intervenes: Solov'ev's Lectures after the Murder of Tsar Alexander II', in: van den Bercken et al. 2000, pp. 297-312.

2. See for instance Peter A. Zaionchkovsky, The Russian Autocracy in Crisis, 1878-1882 (1st publ. in Russian 1964; Gulf Breeze: Academic International Press, 1979).

3. A highly valuable contribution remains the classic work of Franco Venturi, Les intellectuels, le peuple et la revolution: histoire du populisme russe au XIXe siecle (1st publ. in Italian 1952; Paris: Gallimard, 1972) and in particular the chapter devoted to the murder of Alexander II 'Le ler mars 1881'. pp. 1119-1133.

4. Two early collections of materials on March 1st 1881 were published in Byloe, 1906. 3. and Byloe 1918. 4-5. On Solov'ev. see: P. Scegolev. 'Sobytie I-go marta i Vlad. Solov'ev, Byloe, 1906, 3. pp. 48-55: Ibidem. 'Sobytie I marta i Vladimir Solov'ev: novye dokumenty', Byloe, 1918, 4-5, pp. 330-336. The subsequent publications reproduced these sources with minor additions: 'I marta i V.S. Solov'ev', in: coll., I marta 1881 goda: podgotovleno k pecati literaturnoj komissiej kruzka narodovol'cev (Moskva: Izd. Politkatorzanl, 1933), pp. 146-153: 'Sobytie I marta i Vladimir Solov'ev: in: coll., 1 marta 1881 goda: kazn imperatora Aleksandra II: dokumenty i vospominanija (Leningrad: Lenizdat, 1991). pp. 322- 327: Ju.N. Sukharev, 'K issledovaniju zizni i tvorcestva VI. Solov'eva: dokumenty i materialy', Voprosy filosofii 1991, 2. pp. 136-150: I.K. Jancenko. 'Delo o vosprescenii professoru Sankt-Peterburgskogo Universiteta VI. Solov'evu ctenija publicnykh lekcij', M. Smirnov (ed.), Logos 50 (1995), pp. 299-325. To my knowledge there are no Western studies on this specific issue.

5. Mocul'skij 1995, pp. 129-135: Losev 2000, pp. 60-62: Stremooukhoff 1974, pp. 122- 24: S. Solovyov 2000, p. 227. Gaut 1992 devotes a few pages to this crucial event in Solov'ev's life (pp. 51-55).

6. Venturi 1972 2. p. 1048.

7. Nicholas Riasanovsky, A History of Russia (1st publ. 1963: New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 384.

8. It was of crucial importance to silence wide variety or rumours in the province. The murderers were perhaps members of the gentry. in which case this could mean the restoration of serfdom. Another version was that the tsar would proceed to a redistribution of the land among the peasants (S. Val'k. 'Iz zapisnoj knizki arkhivista: posle pervogo marta 1881 g.', Krasnyj arkhiv 45 (1931), 2. pp. 146- 164: pp. 154-156).

9. Venturi 1972 2, p. 1124.

10. This term referred to Loris-Melikov's project although it was in no sense connected to a constitution, but rather only to a very limited form of popular representation.

11. The analysis is drawn from I marta 1881 (1933), p. 22. Except when other sources are mentioned, this work. which quotes numerous journals and newspapers excerpts on the debates (pp. 22-52), forms the basis of the following survey.

12. The most important organs were Porjadok (ed. Stasjulevic), Golos (eds. Kraevskij and Vil'basov), Molva (ed. Poletika), Russkie Vedomosti (ed. unknown), Zemstvo (ed. unknown), Russkaja Mysl' (ed. Jurev), Juridiceskij Vestnik (eds. Gol'cev and Muromcev).

13. This organ of self-government was created in the Muscovite state and disappeared under Peter I.

14. They voiced their opinion mainly in Moskovskie Vedomosti (ed. Katkov), Sovremennye Izvestija (ed. Giljarov-Platonov), Novoe Vremja (ed. Suvorin), and Rus' (ed. I. Aksakov) mainly.

15. Ivan Aksakov (1823-1886) Sohranie socinenij 5 (Moskva: tip. M.G. Volcaninova, 1887), pp. 29, 32.

16. Sankt-Peterburgskie Vedomosti, quoted in I marta 1881 (1933), p. 43. The formulation plays on the ambiguity of the adjective narodnyj, meaning 'popular' as well as 'national'.

17. Ivan Aksakov, 'Po povudu Vysocajsago Manifesta 29 aprelja 1881 g.', first published in Rus', 2 May 1881. Edition used: Sobranie socinenij 5, p. 44.

18. The Slavophile Koselev also defended the idea of local self-government (Stephen Lukashevich, Ivan Aksakov 1823-1886: A Study in Russian Thought and Politics (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1965), p. 154).

19. At that time, Lev Tikhomirov (1852-1923) was considered the theoretician of Narodnaja Volja. The populist Nikolaj Mikhajlovskij (1842-1904) was not against terrorism, but strongly demanded that such acts be justified.

20. 'Pis'mo Isponitel 'nogo Komiteta k Aleksandru III'. Edition used: Byloe, 1906, 3, pp. 33-37: p. 34.

21. Venturi 1972 2, p. 1128-1129.

22. Andrzej Walicki, The Controversy over Capitalism: Studies in the Social Philosophy of the Russian Populists (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1969), p. 103. This wing had been created by Plekhanov and disappeared in the aftermath of March 1st. Other authors who sympathised with socialist and populist views cautiously adopted more moderate views so as to avoid censorship or arrest. For an example, see Nikolaj Scelgunov's (1824-1891) words on the crushing of the mental revolution initiated in the 1860s, in the journal Delo (quoted in I marta 1881 (1933), p. 26). The journals Delo (ed. Scelgunov), Otecestvennye zapiski (ed. Saltykov-Scedrin), Slovo (ed. Zybin) formed a radical coalition of socialist writers and populists (N.R., 'Sobytie I-go marta i Nikolaj Vasil'evic Selgunov', in Byloe, 1906, 3, pp. 41-47).

23. The two lectures, entitled 'Smysl sovremennykh sobytij' and 'Publicnaja lekcija. citannaja professorom Solov'evym v kreditnom obscestve' [abbreviated 'Publicnaja lekcija'] are both published in S. 1989 1. pp. 34-38 and 39-42. The first lecture was first published in SS 3, pp. 417-421.

24. The text was not published on the basis of Solov'ev's manuscript. but on the basis of a lithographic edition. Nevertheless the latter contains the note: 'with approval of the professor' (S. 1989 1, p. 646) and can be thus quoted as being Solov'ev's words.

25. Solov'ev himself indicated the number of attendees in a later declaration to the city governor (published in Scegolev 1918, p. 333). The text of the lecture was edited on the basis of notes taken by an unknown student. As it does not come from the hand of Solov'ev himself. it should be regarded with care and not be attributed literally to Solov'ev. Nevertheless we have the opportunity to get as close as possible to Solovev's original words by taking into account another version of the lecture based on the notes of V.E. Cesikhin-Vetrinskij, published in the commentary of the lecture (S. 1989 1, pp. 649-650). This version distinguishes itself by its compactness and internal coherence. Although it is not as complete as the first version, it provides a more logical understanding of Solov'ev's words.

26. The contents only partly correspond to the programme set by Solov'ev himself for this lecture (see S. 1989 1, commentary pp. 646-647). For this second lecture, Solov'ev had planned to deal with social thought [obscestvennaja mysl') from Nicholas I to Alexander II, and would only in the third lecture broach the issue of the 'present tasks of social thought in Russia' (Ibid., p. 647). Under the pressure of the events of March 1st. the latter formed a core aspect of his lecture of March 28th.

27. 'Publicnaja lekcija', p. 42.

28. Solov'ev's declaration to Baranov (Scegolev 1918, p. 334).

29. Various testimonies were published about the end of the lecture in memoirs decades later (Beaudoin-de Courtenay in Scegolev 1906. pp. 53-54. Slonimskij, op. cit., p. 32. and N. Nikiforov, 'Peterburgskoe studencestvo i Vlad. Sergo Solov'ev', Vestnik Evropy, 1912, 1. pp. 157-186: p. 183). Some refer to threats from the audience and Solov'ev being carried by the crowd. Miljutin even recalled that during the lecture, while the youth or both sexes attracted by socialist teachings enthusiastically approved of it, others nearly killed the 'jurodivogo filosofa' (P.A. Zajonckovskij (ed.). Dnevnik D.A. Miljutina. vol. 4: 1881-1882 (Moskva: n.p., 1950), p. 50). Slonimskij's moderate interpretation seems most plausible. Slonimskij explicitly objected that these outbursts of rage and exuberance from the part of the audience did not occur. This divergence of views requires cautiousness but at least testifies to the huge resonance of Solov'ev's lecture in St. Petersburg public opinion.

30. This letter was first published in Scegolev 1996, pp. 54-55.

31. The three documents were first published in Scegolev 1918, pp. 330-336.

32. Zaionchkovsky 1964, pp. 192-193.

33. Scegolev 1918. p. 334.

34. Ibid., p. 333.

35. The historian and initiator of the Higher Women Courses Konstantin Bestuzev-Rjumin seemingly interceded in favour of Solov'ev (Scegolev 1906, p. 54). Also the grand-prince Vladimir Aleksandrovic and the Minister of Education Andrej Saburov were against harsh measures regarding Solov'ev (from Loris-Melikov's letter to the tsar). Whether Saburov attended Solov'ev's lecture and perhaps even instructed Solov'ev after the lecture to go and see Loris-Melikov is probably untrue (see the colourful story of Beaudoin-de Courtenay, quoted in Scegolev 1906, p. 324).

36. Scegolev 1918, p. 335

37. Ibid.

38. Jancenko 1995, p. 300.

39. Mark Smirnov, 'Materialy k biografii Vladimira Solov'eva', in Logos 50 (1995), pp. 288- 298: p. 297. Whether Solov'ev was subsequently forced to leave the university and his academic career is doubtful, though. It is more likely that 'being a professor was for him simply boring' (Losev 2000, p. (2) and he likely chose to engage in the path of freelance journalism, instead or being absorbed by exams, scientific committees, and being tied regarding the content of his lectures by some university board.

40. 'Publicnaja lekcija', p. 42. The second version or the lecture contains another no less vague formulation: 'we will move apart [otstranimsja] from this circle of mutual murders!' (S. 1989 1. p. 650).

41. 'Publicnaja lekcija', p. 42.

42. Riasanovsky 1993, p. 383. See the classical work by Alain Besancon, Les origines intellectuelles du leninisme (Paris: Calmann-Levy, 1977).

43. 'The speech of the young philosopher in defence of the regicides was an important social event. It agitated the capital.' (Mocul'skij 1995, p. 132).

44. According to the newspaper Porjadok, Solov'ev's lecture generated sympathy for the criminals (Porjadok, 30.03.1881). Quoted in K.P. Pobedonoscev i ego korrespondenty. Pis'ma i zapiski (Moskva & Petrograd: Gos. izd., 1923), vol. 1. p. 174.

45. L.Z. Slonimskij, quoted in Scegolev 1918, p. 331.

46. Report of Baranov to Loris-Melikov (Scegolev 1918, pp. 332-334). The above-mentioned neo-Slavophile Bestuzev-Rjumin nevertheless worked at making the authorities' attitude towards Solov'ev milder.

47. In a letter to Aleksej Suvorin, Aksakov distanced himself from Solov'ev who contended that Aksakov had not drawn his point to its logical conclusion, that is, the duty of the tsar to forgive his father's murderers (quoted in S. 1989 1. pp. 650-651, in the editors' commentary to Solov'ev's second lecture).

48. This last expression becomes clear if we recall that the lecture was part of a series on the history or enlightenment in Russia, in which Solov'ev made a distinction between a 'personal', 'national' and 'universal' dimension. The content or the lecture shows that Solov'ev referred by the term 'personal enlightenment' to the revolutionary movement, and more generally the overwhelming tendency in his time towards individualism. at the cost of ethical demands.

49. The question whether his intervention provoked a debate on the relevance or necessity of abolishing the death penalty remains open. Given the tense climate, these discussions, if they took place, were held in the private sphere. The only piece of information which I have come across is that the liberal jurist S. Zarudnyj sent a letter to Alexander on the very day of the execution with the request to abolish the death penalty (N.A. Troickij, Carizm pod sudom progressivnoj obscestvennosti 1866-1895 gg (Moskva: Mysl', 1979), p. 137). The government did not meet Solov'ev's. Tolstoj's or Zarudnyj's wishes. hut suppressed public execution in May 1881. Rather than the influence of these three authors, it was probably the fear of popular revolt that motivated the government to take such a measure.

50. Troickij 1979, pp. 134-136. Because Tolstoj expressed his views in a private letter, he did not strictly speaking intervene in the public debates, and is not examined as such. Tolstoj held that two unsuccessful approaches had tried to control the revolutionary movement, namely violent repression and weak liberal tolerance. He saw a third path. that of applying God's law of forgiveness, as a result of which many revolutionaries and enemies would turn to him and their ideal would be crushed by the Christian ideal. Worth mentioning is that Tolstoj rejoiced at Solov'ev's intervention and congratulated him (see letter to Strakhov, in I marta 1881 goda (1991), p. 337).

51. 'Smysl sovremennykh sobytij", p. 37.

52. Ibid., p. 36. English translation in Wozniuk 2000, "Christianity and Revolution', pp. 1- : p. 3.

53. 'The people strive to transfer the ideals, which they acknowledged as being true, in which they believe as in existing by themselves. into life. into their untrue reality. to realize them in the non-ideal divine' ("Publicnaja lekcija', p. 41).

54. 'Until the ideal of divine and absolute truth is realised, [ ... ] the people acknowledges the exterior shapes of formation [formy obrazovanija], the exterior milieu, lives in the state' ('Publicnaja lekcija', p. 41).

55. Ibid.

56. Ibid., pp. 40-41. He concluded: 'the people believes in Bogorodica,' Bogorodica is the traditional term referring to the Virgin Mary mother of Jesus Christ. Solov'ev here used the etymological meaning of the term and instigated a shift of meaning to include sophiological elements.

57. These lines also echoed the content of his 10th Lecture on the Humanity of God, which had just been published (Pravaslavnoe Obozrenie, February 1881) and was devoted to the concepts of Sophia and World Soul.

58. I marta 1881 goda (1991), pp. 325-326.

59. 'Publicnaja lekcija', p. 42.

60. Solov'ev laid the stress on the importance of the present in several expressions: 'the present minute represents a unprecedented case so far 'today', 'that is a great moment' ('Publicnaja lekcija', p. 42).
admin
Site Admin
 
Posts: 36135
Joined: Thu Aug 01, 2013 5:21 am

PreviousNext

Return to Ancien Regime

Who is online

Users browsing this forum: No registered users and 25 guests

cron